To the People of the State of New
York:
A FIFTH desideratum, illustrating
the utility of a senate, is the want of a due sense of national character.
Without a select and stable member of the government, the esteem of foreign
powers will not only be forfeited by an unenlightened and variable policy,
proceeding from the causes already mentioned, but the national councils
will not possess that sensibility to the opinion of the world, which is
perhaps not less necessary in order to merit, than it is to obtain, its
respect and confidence.
An attention to the judgment of other
nations is important to every government for two reasons: the one is, that,
independently of the merits of any particular plan or measure, it is desirable,
on various accounts, that it should appear to other nations as the offspring
of a wise and honorable policy; the second is, that in doubtful cases,
particularly where the national councils may be warped by some strong passion
or momentary interest, the presumed or known opinion of the impartial world
may be the best guide that can be followed. What has not America lost by
her want of character with foreign nations; and how many errors and follies
would she not have avoided, if the justice and propriety of her measures
had, in every instance, been previously tried by the light in which they
would probably appear to the unbiased part of mankind?
Yet however requisite a sense of
national character may be, it is evident that it can never be sufficiently
possessed by a numerous and changeable body. It can only be found in a
number so small that a sensible degree of the praise and blame of public
measures may be the portion of each individual; or in an assembly so durably
invested with public trust, that the pride and consequence of its members
may be sensibly incorporated with the reputation and prosperity of the
community. The half-yearly representatives of Rhode Island would probably
have been little affected in their deliberations on the iniquitous measures
of that State, by arguments drawn from the light in which such measures
would be viewed by foreign nations, or even by the sister States; whilst
it can scarcely be doubted that if the concurrence of a select and stable
body had been necessary, a regard to national character alone would have
prevented the calamities under which that misguided people is now laboring.
I add, as a SIXTH defect the want,
in some important cases, of a due responsibility in the government to the
people, arising from that frequency of elections which in other cases produces
this responsibility. This remark will, perhaps, appear not only new, but
paradoxical. It must nevertheless be acknowledged, when explained, to be
as undeniable as it is important.
Responsibility, in order to be reasonable,
must be limited to objects within the power of the responsible party, and
in order to be effectual, must relate to operations of that power, of which
a ready and proper judgment can be formed by the constituents. The objects
of government may be divided into two general classes: the one depending
on measures which have singly an immediate and sensible operation; the
other depending on a succession of well-chosen and well-connected measures,
which have a gradual and perhaps unobserved operation. The importance of
the latter description to the collective and permanent welfare of every
country, needs no explanation. And yet it is evident that an assembly elected
for so short a term as to be unable to provide more than one or two links
in a chain of measures, on which the general welfare may essentially depend,
ought not to be answerable for the final result, any more than a steward
or tenant, engaged for one year, could be justly made to answer for places
or improvements which could not be accomplished in less than half a dozen
years. Nor is it possible for the people to estimate the SHARE of influence
which their annual assemblies may respectively have on events resulting
from the mixed transactions of several years. It is sufficiently difficult
to preserve a personal responsibility in the members of a NUMEROUS body,
for such acts of the body as have an immediate, detached, and palpable
operation on its constituents.
The proper remedy for this defect
must be an additional body in the legislative department, which, having
sufficient permanency to provide for such objects as require a continued
attention, and a train of measures, may be justly and effectually answerable
for the attainment of those objects.
Thus far I have considered the circumstances
which point out the necessity of a well-constructed Senate only as they
relate to the representatives of the people. To a people as little blinded
by prejudice or corrupted by flattery as those whom I address, I shall
not scruple to add, that such an institution may be sometimes necessary
as a defense to the people against their own temporary errors and delusions.
As the cool and deliberate sense of the community ought, in all governments,
and actually will, in all free governments, ultimately prevail over the
views of its rulers; so there are particular moments in public affairs
when the people, stimulated by some irregular passion, or some illicit
advantage, or misled by the artful misrepresentations of interested men,
may call for measures which they themselves will afterwards be the most
ready to lament and condemn. In these critical moments, how salutary will
be the interference of some temperate and respectable body of citizens,
in order to check the misguided career, and to suspend the blow meditated
by the people against themselves, until reason, justice, and truth can
regain their authority over the public mind? What bitter anguish would
not the people of Athens have often escaped if their government had contained
so
provident a safeguard against the tyranny of their own passions? Popular
liberty might then have escaped the indelible reproach of decreeing to
the same citizens the hemlock on one day and statues on the next.
It may be suggested, that a people
spread over an extensive region cannot, like the crowded inhabitants of
a small district, be subject to the infection of violent passions, or to
the danger of combining in pursuit of unjust measures. I am far from denying
that this is a distinction of peculiar importance. I have, on the contrary,
endeavored in a former paper to show, that it is one of the principal recommendations
of a confederated republic. At the same time, this advantage ought not
to be considered as superseding the use of auxiliary precautions. It may
even be remarked, that the same extended situation, which will exempt the
people of America from some of the dangers incident to lesser republics,
will expose them to the inconveniency of remaining for a longer time under
the influence of those misrepresentations which the combined industry of
interested men may succeed in distributing among them.
It adds no small weight to all these
considerations, to recollect that history informs us of no long-lived republic
which had not a senate. Sparta, Rome, and Carthage are, in fact, the only
states to whom that character can be applied. In each of the two first
there was a senate for life. The constitution of the senate in the last
is less known. Circumstantial evidence makes it probable that it was not
different in this particular from the two others. It is at least certain,
that it had some quality or other which rendered it an anchor against popular
fluctuations; and that a smaller council, drawn out of the senate, was
appointed not only for life, but filled up vacancies itself. These examples,
though as unfit for the imitation, as they are repugnant to the genius,
of America, are, notwithstanding, when compared with the fugitive and turbulent
existence of other ancient republics, very instructive proofs of the necessity
of some institution that will blend stability with liberty. I am not unaware
of the circumstances which distinguish the American from other popular
governments, as well ancient as modern; and which render extreme circumspection
necessary, in reasoning from the one case to the other. But after allowing
due weight to this consideration, it may still be maintained, that there
are many points of similitude which render these examples not unworthy
of our attention. Many of the defects, as we have seen, which can only
be supplied by a senatorial institution, are common to a numerous assembly
frequently elected by the people, and to the people themselves. There are
others peculiar to the former, which require the control of such an institution.
The people can never wilfully betray their own interests; but they may
possibly be betrayed by the representatives of the people; and the danger
will be evidently greater where the whole legislative trust is lodged in
the hands of one body of men, than where the concurrence of separate and
dissimilar bodies is required in every public act.
The difference most relied on, between
the American and other republics, consists in the principle of representation;
which is the pivot on which the former move, and which is supposed to have
been unknown to the latter, or at least to the ancient part of them. The
use which has been made of this difference, in reasonings contained in
former papers, will have shown that I am disposed neither to deny its existence
nor to undervalue its importance. I feel the less restraint, therefore,
in observing, that the position concerning the ignorance of the ancient
governments on the subject of representation, is by no means precisely
true in the latitude commonly given to it. Without entering into a disquisition
which here would be misplaced, I will refer to a few known facts, in support
of what I advance.
In the most pure democracies of Greece,
many of the executive functions were performed, not by the people themselves,
but by officers elected by the people, and REPRESENTING the people in their
EXECUTIVE capacity.
Prior to the reform of Solon, Athens
was governed by nine Archons, annually ELECTED BY THE PEOPLE AT LARGE.
The degree of power delegated to them seems to be left in great obscurity.
Subsequent to that period, we find an assembly, first of four, and afterwards
of six hundred members, annually ELECTED BY THE PEOPLE; and PARTIALLY representing
them in their LEGISLATIVE capacity, since they were not only associated
with the people in the function of making laws, but had the exclusive right
of originating legislative propositions to the people. The senate of Carthage,
also, whatever might be its power, or the duration of its appointment,
appears to have been ELECTIVE by the suffrages of the people. Similar instances
might be traced in most, if not all the popular governments of antiquity.
Lastly, in Sparta we meet with the
Ephori, and in Rome with the Tribunes; two bodies, small indeed in numbers,
but annually ELECTED BY THE WHOLE BODY OF THE PEOPLE, and considered as
the REPRESENTATIVES of the people, almost in their PLENIPOTENTIARY capacity.
The Cosmi of Crete were also annually ELECTED BY THE PEOPLE, and have been
considered by some authors as an institution analogous to those of Sparta
and Rome, with this difference only, that in the election of that representative
body the right of suffrage was communicated to a part only of the people.
From these facts, to which many others
might be added, it is clear that the principle of representation was neither
unknown to the ancients nor wholly overlooked in their political constitutions.
The true distinction between these and the American governments, lies IN
THE TOTAL EXCLUSION OF THE PEOPLE, IN THEIR COLLECTIVE CAPACITY, from any
share in the LATTER, and not in the TOTAL EXCLUSION OF THE REPRESENTATIVES
OF THE PEOPLE from the administration of the FORMER. The distinction, however,
thus qualified, must be admitted to leave a most advantageous superiority
in favor of the United States. But to insure to this advantage its full
effect, we must be careful not to separate it from the other advantage,
of an extensive territory. For it cannot be believed, that any form of
representative government could have succeeded within the narrow limits
occupied by the democracies of Greece.
In answer to all these arguments,
suggested by reason, illustrated by examples, and enforced by our own experience,
the jealous adversary of the Constitution will probably content himself
with repeating, that a senate appointed not immediately by the people,
and for the term of six years, must gradually acquire a dangerous pre-eminence
in the government, and finally transform it into a tyrannical aristocracy.
To this general answer, the general
reply ought to be sufficient, that liberty may be endangered by the abuses
of liberty as well as by the abuses of power; that there are numerous instances
of the former as well as of the latter; and that the former, rather than
the latter, are apparently most to be apprehended by the United States.
But a more particular reply may be given.
Before such a revolution can be effected,
the Senate, it is to be observed, must in the first place corrupt itself;
must next corrupt the State legislatures; must then corrupt the House of
Representatives; and must finally corrupt the people at large. It is evident
that the Senate must be first corrupted before it can attempt an establishment
of tyranny. Without corrupting the State legislatures, it cannot prosecute
the attempt, because the periodical change of members would otherwise regenerate
the whole body. Without exerting the means of corruption with equal success
on the House of Representatives, the opposition of that coequal branch
of the government would inevitably defeat the attempt; and without corrupting
the people themselves, a succession of new representatives would speedily
restore all things to their pristine order. Is there any man who can seriously
persuade himself that the proposed Senate can, by any possible means within
the compass of human address, arrive at the object of a lawless ambition,
through all these obstructions?
If reason condemns the suspicion,
the same sentence is pronounced by experience. The constitution of Maryland
furnishes the most apposite example. The Senate of that State is elected,
as the federal Senate will be, indirectly by the people, and for a term
less by one year only than the federal Senate. It is distinguished, also,
by the remarkable prerogative of filling up its own vacancies within the
term of its appointment, and, at the same time, is not under the control
of any such rotation as is provided for the federal Senate. There are some
other lesser distinctions, which would expose the former to colorable objections,
that do not lie against the latter. If the federal Senate, therefore, really
contained the danger which has been so loudly proclaimed, some symptoms
at least of a like danger ought by this time to have been betrayed by the
Senate of Maryland, but no such symptoms have appeared. On the contrary,
the jealousies at first entertained by men of the same description with
those who view with terror the correspondent part of the federal Constitution,
have been gradually extinguished by the progress of the experiment; and
the Maryland constitution is daily deriving, from the salutary operation
of this part of it, a reputation in which it will probably not be rivalled
by that of any State in the Union.
But if any thing could silence the
jealousies on this subject, it ought to be the British example. The Senate
there instead of being elected for a term of six years, and of being unconfined
to particular families or fortunes, is an hereditary assembly of opulent
nobles. The House of Representatives, instead of being elected for two
years, and by the whole body of the people, is elected for seven years,
and, in very great proportion, by a very small proportion of the people.
Here, unquestionably, ought to be seen in full display the aristocratic
usurpations and tyranny which are at some future period to be exemplified
in the United States. Unfortunately, however, for the anti-federal argument,
the British history informs us that this hereditary assembly has not been
able to defend itself against the continual encroachments of the House
of Representatives; and that it no sooner lost the support of the monarch,
than it was actually crushed by the weight of the popular branch.
As far as antiquity can instruct
us on this subject, its examples support the reasoning which we have employed.
In Sparta, the Ephori, the annual representatives of the people, were found
an overmatch for the senate for life, continually gained on its authority
and finally drew all power into their own hands. The Tribunes of Rome,
who were the representatives of the people, prevailed, it is well known,
in almost every contest with the senate for life, and in the end gained
the most complete triumph over it. The fact is the more remarkable, as
unanimity was required in every act of the Tribunes, even after their number
was augmented to ten. It proves the irresistible force possessed by that
branch of a free government, which has the people on its side. To these
examples might be added that of Carthage, whose senate, according to the
testimony of Polybius, instead of drawing all power into its vortex, had,
at the commencement of the second Punic War, lost almost the whole of its
original portion.
Besides the conclusive evidence resulting
from this assemblage of facts, that the federal Senate will never be able
to transform itself, by gradual usurpations, into an independent and aristocratic
body, we are warranted in believing, that if such a revolution should ever
happen from causes which the foresight of man cannot guard against, the
House of Representatives, with the people on their side, will at all times
be able to bring back the Constitution to its primitive form and principles.
Against the force of the immediate representatives of the people, nothing
will be able to maintain even the constitutional authority of the Senate,
but such a display of enlightened policy, and attachment to the public
good, as will divide with that branch of the legislature the affections
and support of the entire body of the people themselves.
PUBLIUS. |