Permanent
E-mail Addresses Freethought Audio
Tapes Products for Freethinkers

Library: Historical Documents: Charles Darwin: Descent of Man: Chapter 4


This file has been made available by the Bank Of Wisdom.

Descent of Man [ 1871 ]

Charles Darwin [ 1809 - 1882 ]

 

Chapter IV - Comparison of the Mental Powers of Man and the Lower Animals (continued)




  I FULLY subscribe to the judgment of those writers* who maintain

that of all the differences between man and the lower animals, the

moral sense or conscience is by far the most important. This sense, as

Mackintosh*(2) remarks, "has a rightful supremacy over every other

principle of human action"; it is summed up in that short but

imperious word ought, so full of high significance. It is the most

noble of all the attributes of man, leading him without a moment's

hesitation to risk his life for that of a fellow-creature; or after

due deliberation, impelled simply by the deep feeling of right or

duty, to sacrifice it in some great cause. Immanuel Kant exclaims,

"Duty! Wondrous thought, that workest neither by fond insinuation,

flattery, nor by any threat, but merely by holding up thy naked law in

the soul, and so extorting for thyself always reverence, if not always

obedience; before whom all appetites are dumb, however secretly they

rebel; whence thy original?"*(3)



  * See, for instance, on this subject, Quatrefages, Unite de l'Espece

Humaine, 1861, p. 21, &c.

  *(2) Dissertation an Ethical Philosophy, 1837, p. 231, &c.

  *(3) Metaphysics of Ethics translated by J. W. Semple, Edinburgh,

1836, p. 136.



  This great question has been discussed by many writers* of

consummate ability; and my sole excuse for touching on it, is the

impossibility of here passing it over; and because, as far as I

know, no one has approached it exclusively from the side of natural

history. The investigation possesses, also, some independent interest,

as an attempt to see how far the study of the lower animals throws

light on one of the highest psychical faculties of man.



  * Mr. Bain gives a list (Mental and Moral Science, 1868, pp.

543-725) of twenty-six British authors who have written on this

subject, and whose names are familiar to every reader; to these, Mr.

Bain's own name, and those of Mr. Lecky, Mr. Shadworth Hodgson, Sir J.

Lubbock, and others, might be added.



  The following proposition seems to me in a high degree probable-

namely, that any animal whatever, endowed with well-marked social

instincts,* the parental and filial affections being here included,

would inevitably acquire a moral sense or conscience, as soon as its

intellectual powers had become as well, or nearly as well developed,

as in man. For, firstly, the social instincts lead an animal to take

pleasure in the society of its fellows, to feel a certain amount of

sympathy with them, and to perform various services for them. The

services may be of a definite and evidently instinctive nature; or

there may be only a wish and readiness, as with most of the higher

social animals, to aid their fellows in certain general ways. But

these feelings and services are by no means extended to all the

individuals of the same species, only to those of the same

association. Secondly, as soon as the mental faculties had become

highly developed, images of all past actions and motives would be

incessantly passing through the brain of each individual: and that

feeling of dissatisfaction, or even misery, which invariably

results, as we shall hereafter see, from any unsatisfied instinct,

would arise, as often as it was perceived that the enduring and always

present social instinct had yielded to some other instinct, at the

time stronger, but neither enduring in its nature, nor leaving

behind it a very vivid impression. It is clear that many instinctive

desires, such as that of hunger, are in their nature of short

duration; and after being satisfied, are not readily or vividly

recalled. Thirdly, after the power of language had been acquired,

and the wishes of the community could be expressed, the common opinion

how each member ought to act for the public good, would naturally

become in a paramount degree the guide to action. But it should be

borne in mind that however great weight we may attribute to public

opinion, our regard for the approbation and disapprobation of our

fellows depends on sympathy, which, as we shall see, forms an

essential part of the social instinct, and is indeed its

foundation-stone. Lastly, habit in the individual would ultimately

play a very important part in guiding the conduct of each member;

for the social instinct, together with sympathy, is, like any other

instinct, greatly strengthened by habit, and so consequently would

be obedience to the wishes and judgment of the community. These

several subordinate propositions must now be discussed, and some of

them at considerable length.



  * Sir B. Brodie, after observing that man is a social animal

(Psychological Enquiries, 1854, p. 192), asks the pregnant question,

"Ought not this to settle the disputed question as to the existence of

a moral sense?" Similar ideas have probably occurred to many

persons, as they did long ago to Marcus Aurelius. Mr. J. S. Mill

speaks, in his celebrated work, Utilitarianism, pp. 459, 460, of the

social feelings as a "powerful natural sentiment," and as "the natural

basis of sentiment for utilitarian morality." Again he says, "Like the

other acquired capacities above referred to, the moral faculty, if not

a part of our nature, is a natural out-growth from it; capable, like

them, in a certain small degree of springing up spontaneously." But in

opposition to all this, he also remarks, "If, as in my own belief, the

moral feelings are not innate, but acquired, they are not for that

reason less natural." It is with hesitation that I venture to differ

at all from so profound a thinker, but it can hardly be disputed

that the social feelings are instinctive or innate in the lower

animals; and why should they not be so in man? Mr. Bain (see, for

instance, The Emotions and the Will, 1865, p. 481) and others

believe that the moral sense is acquired by each individual during his

lifetime. On the general theory of evolution this is at least

extremely improbable. The ignoring of all transmitted mental qualities

will, as it seems to me, be hereafter judged as a most serious blemish

in the works of Mr. Mill.



  It may be well first to premise that I do not wish to maintain

that any strictly social animal, if its intellectual faculties were to

become as active and as highly developed as in man, would acquire

exactly the same moral sense as ours. In the same manner as various

animals have some sense of beauty, though they admire widely-different

objects, so they might have a sense of right and wrong, though led

by it to follow widely different lines of conduct. If, for instance,

to take an extreme case, men were reared under precisely the same

conditions as hive-bees, there can hardly be a doubt that our

unmarried females would, like the worker-bees, think it a sacred

duty to kill their brothers, and mothers would strive to kill their

fertile daughters; and no one would think of interfering.*

Nevertheless, the bee, or any other social animal, would gain in our

supposed case, as it appears to me, some feeling of right or wrong, or

a conscience. For each individual would have an inward sense of

possessing certain stronger or more enduring instincts, and others

less strong or enduring; so that there would often be a struggle as to

which impulse should be followed; and satisfaction, dissatisfaction,

or even misery would be felt, as past impressions were compared during

their incessant passage through the mind. In this case an inward

monitor would tell the animal that it would have been better to have

followed the one impulse rather than the other. The one course ought

to have been followed, and the other ought not; the one would have

been right and the other wrong; but to these terms I shall recur.



  Mr. H. Sidgwick remarks, in an able discussion on this subject

(the Academy, June 15, 1872, p. 231), "A superior bee, we may feel

sure, would aspire to a milder solution of the popular question."

Judging, however, from the habits of many or most savages, man

solves the problem by female infanticide, polyandry and promiscuous

intercourse; therefore it may well be doubted whether it would be by a

milder method. Miss Cobbe, in commenting ("Darwinism in Morals,"

Theological Review, April, 1872, pp. 188-191) on the same

illustration, says, the principles of social duty would be thus

reversed; and by this, I presume, she means that the fulfillment of

a social duty would tend to the injury of individuals; but she

overlooks the fact, which she would doubtless admit, that the

instincts of the bee have been acquired for the good of the community.

She goes so far as to say that if the theory of ethics advocated in

this chapter were ever generally accepted, "I cannot but believe

that in the hour of their triumph would be sounded the knell of the

virtue of mankind!" It is to be hoped that the belief in the

permanence of virtue on this earth is not held by many persons on so

weak a tenure.



  Sociability.- Animals of many kinds are social; we find even

distinct species living together; for example, some American

monkeys; and united flocks of rooks, jackdaws, and starlings. Man

shews the same feeling in his strong love for the dog, which the dog

returns with interest. Every one must have noticed how miserable

horses, dogs, sheep, &c., are when separated from their companions,

and what strong mutual affection the two former kinds, at least,

shew on their reunion. It is curious to speculate on the feelings of a

dog, who will rest peacefully for hours in a room with his master or

any of the family, without the least notice being taken of him; but if

left for a short time by himself, barks or howls dismally. We will

confine our attention to the higher social animals; and pass over

insects, although some of these are social, and aid one another in

many important ways. The most common mutual service in the higher

animals is to warn one another of danger by means of the united senses

of all. Every sportsman knows, as Dr. Jaeger remarks,* how difficult

it is to approach animals in a herd or troop. Wild horses and cattle

do not, I believe, make any danger-signal; but the attitude of any one

of them who first discovers an enemy, warns the others. Rabbits

stamp loudly on the ground with their hindfeet as a signal: sheep

and chamois do the same with their forefeet, uttering likewise a

whistle. Many birds, and some mammals, post sentinels, which in the

case of seals are said*(2) generally to be the females. The leader

of a troop of monkeys acts as the sentinel, and utters cries

expressive both of danger and of safety.*(3) Social animals perform

many little services for each other: horses nibble, and cows lick each

other, on any spot which itches: monkeys search each other for

external parasites; and Brehm states that after a troop of the

Cercopithecus griseoviridis has rushed through a thorny brake, each

monkey stretches itself on a branch, and another monkey sitting by,

"conscientiously" examines its fur, and extracts every thorn or burr.



  * Die Darwin'sche Theorie, s. 101.

  *(2) Mr. R. Brown in Proc. Zoolog. Soc., 1868, p. 409.

  *(3) Brehm, Illustriertes Thierleben, B. i., 1864, ss. 52, 79. For

the case of the monkeys extracting thorns from each other, see s.

54. With respect to the Hamadryas turning over stones, the fact is

given (s. 76), on the evidence of Alvarez, whose observations Brehm

thinks quite trustworthy. For the cases of the old male baboons

attacking the dogs, see s. 79; and with respect to the eagle, s. 56.



  Animals also render more important services to one another: thus

wolves and some other beasts of prey hunt in packs, and aid one

another in attacking their victims. Pelicans fish in concert. The

Hamadryas baboons turn over stones to find insects, &c.; and when they

come to a large one, as many as can stand round, turn it over together

and share the booty. Social animals mutually defend each other. Bull

bisons in N. America, when there is danger, drive the cows and

calves into the middle of the herd, whilst they defend the outside.

I shall also in a future chapter give an account of two young wild

bulls at Chillingham attacking an old one in concert, and of two

stallions together trying to drive away a third stallion from a

troop of mares. In Abyssinia, Brehm encountered a great troop of

baboons who were crossing a valley; some had already ascended the

opposite mountain, and some were still in the valley; the latter

were attacked by the dogs, but the old males immediately hurried

down from the rocks, and with mouths widely opened, roared so

fearfully, that the dogs quickly drew back. They were again encouraged

to the attack; but by this time all the baboons had reascended the

heights, excepting a young one, about six months old, who, loudly

calling for aid, climbed on a block of rock, and was surrounded. Now

one of the largest males, a true hero, came down again from the

mountain, slowly went to the young one, coaxed him, and triumphantly

led him away- the dogs being too much astonished to make an attack.

I cannot resist giving another scene which was witnessed by this

same naturalist; an eagle seized a young Cercopithecus, which, by

clinging to a branch, was not at once carried off; it cried loudly for

assistance, upon which the other members of the troop, with much

uproar, rushed to the rescue, surrounded the eagle, and pulled out

so many feathers, that he no longer thought of his prey, but only

how to escape. This eagle, as Brehm remarks, assuredly would never

again attack a single monkey of a troop.*



  * Mr. Belt gives the case of a spider-monkey (Ateles) in

Nicaragua, which was heard screaming for nearly two hours in the

forest, and was found with an eagle perched close by it. The bird

apparently feared to attack as long as it remained face to face; and

Mr. Belt believes, from what he has seen of the habits of these

monkeys, that they protect themselves from eagles by keeping two or

three together. The Naturalist in Nicaragua, 1874, p. 118.



  It is certain that associated animals have a feeling of love for

each other, which is not felt by non-social adult animals. How far

in most cases they actually sympathise in the pains and pleasures of

others, is more doubtful, especially with respect to pleasures. Mr.

Buxton, however, who had excellent means of observation,* states

that his macaws, which lived free in Norfolk, took "an extravagant

interest" in a pair with a nest; and whenever the female left it,

she was surrounded by a troop "screaming horrible acclamations in

her honour." It is often difficult to judge whether animals have any

feeling for the sufferings of others of their kind. Who can say what

cows feel, when they surround and stare intently on a dying or dead

companion; apparently, however, as Houzeau remarks, they feel no pity.

That animals sometimes are far from feeling any sympathy is too

certain; for they will expel a wounded animal from the herd, or gore

or worry it to death. This is almost the blackest fact in natural

history, unless, indeed, the explanation which has been suggested is

true, that their instinct or reason leads them to expel an injured

companion, lest beasts of prey, including man, should be tempted to

follow the troop. In this case their conduct is not much worse than

that of the North American Indians, who leave their feeble comrades to

perish on the plains; or the Fijians, who, when their parents get old,

or fall ill, bury them alive.*(2)



  * Annals and Magazine of Natural History, November, 1868, p. 382.

  *(2) Sir J. Lubbock, Prehistoric Times, 2nd ed., p. 446.



  Many animals, however, certainly sympathise with each other's

distress or danger. This is the case even with birds. Captain

Stansbury* found on a salt lake in Utah an old and completely blind

pelican, which was very fat, and must have been well fed for a long

time by his companions. Mr. Blyth, as he informs me, saw Indian

crows feeding two or three of their companions which were blind; and I

have heard of an analogous case with the domestic cock. We may, if

we choose, call these actions instinctive; but such cases are much too

rare for the development of any special instinct.*(2) I have myself

seen a dog, who never passed a cat who lay sick in a basket, and was a

great friend of his, without giving her a few licks with his tongue,

the surest sign of kind feeling in a dog.



  * As quoted by Mr. L. H. Morgan, The American Beaver, 1868, p.

272. Capt. Stansbury also gives an interesting account of the manner

in which a very young pelican, carried away by a strong stream, was

guided and encouraged in its attempts to reach the shore by half a

dozen old birds.

  *(2) As Mr. Bain states, "Effective aid to a sufferer springs from

sympathy proper": Mental and Moral Science, 1868, p. 245.



  It must be called sympathy that leads a courageous dog to fly at any

one who strikes his master, as he certainly will. I saw a person

pretending to beat a lady, who had a very timid little dog on her lap,

and the trial had never been made before; the little creature

instantly jumped away, but after the pretended beating was over, it

was really pathetic to see how perseveringly he tried to lick his

mistress's face, and comfort her. Brehm* states that when a baboon

in confinement was pursued to be punished, the others tried to protect

him. It must have been sympathy in the cases above given which led the

baboons and Cercopitheci to defend their young comrades from the

dogs and the eagle. I will give only one other instance of sympathetic

and heroic conduct, in the case of a little American monkey. Several

years ago a keeper at the Zoological Gardens showed me some deep and

scarcely healed wounds on the nape of his own neck, inflicted on

him, whilst kneeling on the floor, by a fierce baboon. The little

American monkey, who was a warm friend of this keeper, lived in the

same compartment, and was dreadfully afraid of the great baboon.

Nevertheless, as soon as he saw his friend in peril, he rushed to

the rescue, and by screams and bites so distracted the baboon that the

man was able to escape, after, as the surgeon thought, running great

risk of his life.



  * Illustriertes Thierleben, B. i., s. 85.



  Besides love and sympathy, animals exhibit other qualities connected

with the social instincts, which in us would be called moral; and I

agree with Agassiz* that dogs possess something very like a

conscience.



  * De l'Espece et de la Classe, 1869, p. 97.



  Dogs possess some power of self-command, and this does not appear to

be wholly the result of fear. As Braubach* remarks, they will

refrain from stealing food in the absence of their master. They have

long been accepted as the very type of fidelity and obedience. But the

elephant is likewise very faithful to his driver or keeper, and

probably considers him as the leader of the herd. Dr. Hooker informs

me that an elephant, which he was riding in India, became so deeply

bogged that he remained stuck fast until the next day, when he was

extricated by men with ropes. Under such circumstances elephants

will seize with their trunks any object, dead or alive, to place under

their knees, to prevent their sinking deeper in the mud; and the

driver was dreadfully afraid lest the animal should have seized Dr.

Hooker and crushed him to death. But the driver himself, as Dr. Hooker

was assured, ran no risk. This forbearance under an emergency so

dreadful for a heavy animal, is a wonderful proof of noble

fidelity.*(2)



  * Die Darwin'sche Art-Lehre, 1869, s. 54.

  *(2) See also Hooker's Himalayan Journals, vol. ii., 1854, p. 333.



  All animals living in a body, which defend themselves or attack

their enemies in concert, must indeed be in some degree faithful to

one another; and those that follow a leader must be in some degree

obedient. When the baboons in Abyssinia* plunder a garden, they

silently follow their leader; and if an imprudent young animal makes a

noise, he receives a slap from the others to teach him silence and

obedience. Mr. Galton, who has had excellent opportunities for

observing the half-wild cattle in S. Africa, says,*(2) that they

cannot endure even a momentary separation from the herd. They are

essentially slavish, and accept the common determination, seeking no

better lot than to be led by any one ox who has enough self-reliance

to accept the position. The men who break in these animals for

harness, watch assiduously for those who, by grazing apart, shew a

self-reliant disposition, and these they train as fore-oxen. Mr.

Galton adds that such animals are rare and valuable; and if many

were born they would soon be eliminated, as lions are always on the

look-out for the individuals which wander from the herd.



  * Brehm, Illustriertes Thierleben, B. i., s. 76

  *(2) See his extremely interesting paper on "Gregariousness in

Cattle, and in Man," Macmillan's Magazine, Feb., 1871, p. 353.



  With respect to the impulse which leads certain animals to associate

together, and to aid one another in many ways, we may infer that in

most cases they are impelled by the same sense of satisfaction or

pleasure which they experience in performing other instinctive

actions; or by the same sense of dissatisfaction as when other

instinctive actions are checked. We see this in innumerable instances,

and it is illustrated in a striking manner by the acquired instincts

of our domesticated animals; thus a young shepherd-dog delights in

driving and running round a flock of sheep, but not in worrying

them; a young fox-hound delights in hunting a fox, whilst some other

kinds of dogs, as I have witnessed, utterly disregard foxes. What a

strong feeling of inward satisfaction must impel a bird, so full of

activity, to brood day after day over her eggs. Migratory birds are

quite miserable if stopped from migrating; perhaps they enjoy starting

on their long flight; but it is hard to believe that the poor pinioned

goose, described by Audubon, which started on foot at the proper

time for its journey of probably more than a thousand miles, could

have felt any joy in doing so. Some instincts are determined solely by

painful feelings, as by fear, which leads to self-preservation, and is

in some cases directed towards special enemies. No one, I presume, can

analyse the sensations of pleasure or pain. In many instances,

however, it is probable that instincts are persistently followed

from the mere force of inheritance, without the stimulus of either

pleasure or pain. A young pointer, when it first scents game,

apparently cannot help pointing. A squirrel in a cage who pats the

nuts which it cannot eat, as if to bury them in the ground, can hardly

be thought to act thus, either from pleasure or pain. Hence the common

assumption that men must be impelled to every action by experiencing

some pleasure or pain may be erroneous. Although a habit may be

blindly and implicitly followed, independently of any pleasure or pain

felt at the moment, yet if it be forcibly and abruptly checked, a

vague sense of dissatisfaction is generally experienced.

  It has often been assumed that animals were in the first place

rendered social, and that they feel as a consequence uncomfortable

when separated from each other, and comfortable whilst together; but

it is a more probable view that these sensations were first developed,

in order that those animals which would profit by living in society,

should be induced to live together, in the same manner as the sense of

hunger and the pleasure of eating were, no doubt, first acquired in

order to induce animals to eat. The feeling of pleasure from society

is probably an extension of the parental or filial affections, since

the social instinct seems to be developed by the young remaining for a

long time with their parents; and this extension may be attributed

in part to habit, but chiefly to natural selection. With those animals

which were benefited by living in close association, the individuals

which took the greatest pleasure in society would best escape

various dangers, whilst those that cared least for their comrades, and

lived solitary, would perish in greater numbers. With respect to the

origin of the parental and filial affections, which apparently lie

at the base of the social instincts, we know not the steps by which

they have been gained; but we may infer that it has been to a large

extent through natural selection. So it has almost certainly been with

the unusual and opposite feeling of hatred between the nearest

relations, as with the worker-bees which kill their brother drones,

and with the queen-bees which kill their daughter-queens; the desire

to destroy their nearest relations having been in this case of service

to the community. Parental affection, or some feeling which replaces

it, has been developed in certain animals extremely low in the

scale, for example, in star-fishes and spiders. It is also

occasionally present in a few members alone in a whole group of

animals, as in the genus Forficula, or earwigs.

  The all-important emotion of sympathy is distinct from that of love.

A mother may passionately love her sleeping and passive infant, but

she can hardly at such times be said to feel sympathy for it. The love

of a man for his dog is distinct from sympathy, and so is that of a

dog for his master. Adam Smith formerly argued, as has Mr. Bain

recently, that the basis of sympathy lies in our strong

retentiveness of former states of pain or pleasure. Hence, "the

sight of another person enduring hunger, cold, fatigue, revives in

us some recollection of these states, which are painful even in idea."

We are thus impelled to relieve the sufferings of another, in order

that our own painful feelings may be at the same time relieved. In

like manner we are led to participate in the pleasures of others.* But

I cannot see how this view explains the fact that sympathy is excited,

in an immeasurably stronger degree, by a beloved, than by an

indifferent person. The mere sight of suffering, independently of

love, would suffice to call up in us vivid recollections and

associations. The explanation may lie in the fact that, with all

animals, sympathy is directed solely towards the members of the same

community, and therefore towards known, and more or less beloved

members, but not to all the individuals of the same species. This fact

is not more surprising than that the fears of many animals should be

directed against special enemies. Species which are not social, such

as lions and tigers, no doubt feel sympathy for the suffering of their

own young, but not for that of any other animal. With mankind,

selfishness, experience, and imitation, probably add, as Mr. Bain

has shown, to the power of sympathy; for we are led by the hope of

receiving good in return to perform acts of sympathetic kindness to

others; and sympathy is much strengthened by habit. In however complex

a manner this feeling may have originated, as it is one of high

importance to all those animals which aid and defend one another, it

will have been increased through natural selection; for those

communities, which included the greatest number of the most

sympathetic members, would flourish best, and rear the greatest number

of offspring.



  * See the first and striking chapter in Adam Smith's Theory of Moral

Sentiments. Also Mr. Bain's Mental and Moral Science, 1868, pp. 244,

and 275-282. Mr. Bain states, that, "Sympathy is, indirectly, a source

of pleasure to the sympathiser"; and he accounts for this through

reciprocity. He remarks that "The person benefited, or others in his

stead, may make up, by sympathy and good offices returned, for all the

sacrifice." But if, as appears to be the case, sympathy is strictly an

instinct, its exercise would give direct pleasure, in the same

manner as the exercise, as before remarked, of almost every other

instinct.



  It is, however, impossible to decide in many cases whether certain

social instincts have been acquired through natural selection, or

are the indirect result of other instincts and faculties, such as

sympathy, reason, experience, and a tendency to imitation; or again,

whether they are simply the result of long-continued habit. So

remarkable an instinct as the placing sentinels to warn the

community of danger, can hardly have been the indirect result of any

of these faculties; it must, therefore, have been directly acquired.

On the other hand, the habit followed by the males of some social

animals of defending the community, and of attacking their enemies

or their prey in concert, may perhaps have originated from mutual

sympathy; but courage, and in most cases strength, must have been

previously acquired, probably through natural selection.

  Of the various instincts and habits, some are much stronger than

others; that is, some either give more pleasure in their

performance, and more distress in their prevention, than others; or,

which is probably quite as important, they are, through inheritance,

more persistently followed, without exciting any special feeling of

pleasure or pain. We are ourselves conscious that some habits are much

more difficult to cure or change than others. Hence a struggle may

often be observed in animals between different instincts, or between

an instinct and some habitual disposition; as when a dog rushes

after a hare, is rebuked, pauses, hesitates, pursues again, or returns

ashamed to his master; or as between the love of a female dog for

her young puppies and for her master,-for she may be seen to slink

away to them, as if half ashamed of not accompanying her master. But

the most curious instance known to me of one instinct getting the

better of another, is the migratory instinct conquering the maternal

instinct. The former is wonderfully strong; a confined bird will at

the proper season beat her breast against the wires of her cage, until

it is bare and bloody. It causes young salmon to leap out of the fresh

water, in which they could continue to exist, and thus unintentionally

to commit suicide. Every one knows how strong the maternal instinct

is, leading even timid birds to face great danger, though with

hesitation, and in opposition to the instinct of self-preservation.

Nevertheless, the migratory instinct is so powerful, that late in

the autumn swallows, house-martins, and swifts frequently desert their

tender young, leaving them to perish miserably in their nests.*



  * This fact, the Rev. L. Jenyns states (see his edition of White's

Nat. Hist. of Selborne, 1853, p. 204), was first recorded by the

illustrious Jenner, in Phil. Transact., 1824, and has since been

confirmed by several observers, especially by Mr. Blackwall. This

latter careful observer examined, late in the autumn, during two

years, thirty-six nests; he found that twelve contained young dead

birds, five contained eggs on the point of being hatched, and three,

eggs not nearly hatched. Many birds, not yet old enough for a

prolonged flight, are likewise deserted and left behind. See

Blackwall, Researches in Zoology, 1834, pp. 108, 118. For some

additional evidence, although this is not wanted, see Leroy, Lettres

Phil., 1802, p. 217. For swifts, Gould's Introduction to the Birds

of Great Britain, 1823, p. 5. Similar cases have been observed in

Canada by Mr. Adams; Pop. Science Review, July, 1873, p. 283.



  We can perceive that an instinctive impulse, if it be in any way

more beneficial to a species than some other or opposed instinct,

would be rendered the more potent of the two through natural

selection; for the individuals which had it most strongly developed

would survive in larger numbers. Whether this is the case with the

migratory in comparison with the maternal instinct, may be doubted.

The great persistence, or steady action of the former at certain

seasons of the year during the whole day, may give it for a time

paramount force.

  Man a social animal.- Every one will admit that man is a social

being. We see this in his dislike of solitude, and in his wish for

society beyond that of his own family. Solitary confinement is one

of the severest punishments which can be inflicted. Some authors

suppose that man primevally lived in single families; but at the

present day, though single families, or only two or three together,

roam the solitudes of some savage lands, they always, as far as I

can discover, hold friendly relations with other families inhabiting

the same district. Such families occasionally meet in council, and

unite for their common defence. It is no argument against savage man

being a social animal, that the tribes inhabiting adjacent districts

are almost always at war with each other; for the social instincts

never extend to all the individuals of the same species. Judging

from the analogy of the majority of the Quadrumana, it is probable

that the early ape-like progenitors of man were likewise social; but

this is not of much importance for us. Although man, as he now exists,

has few special instincts, having lost any which his early progenitors

may have possessed, this is no reason why he should not have

retained from an extremely remote period some degree of instinctive

love and sympathy for his fellows. We are indeed all conscious that we

do possess such sympathetic feelings;* but our consciousness does

not tell us whether they are instinctive, having originated long ago

in the same manner as with the lower animals, or whether they have

been acquired by each of us during our early years. As man is a social

animal, it is almost certain that he would inherit a tendency to be

faithful to his comrades, and obedient to the leader of his tribe; for

these qualities are common to most social animals. He would

consequently possess some capacity for self-command. He would from

an inherited tendency be willing to defend, in concert with others,

his fellow-men; and would be ready to aid them in any way, which did

not too greatly interfere with his own welfare or his own strong

desires.



  * Hume remarks (An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals,

ed. of 1751, p. 132), "There seems a necessity for confessing that the

happiness and misery of others are not spectacles altogether

indifferent to us, but that the view of the former... communicates a

secret joy; the appearance of the latter... throws a melancholy damp

over the imagination."



  The social animals which stand at the bottom of the scale are guided

almost exclusively, and those which stand higher in the scale are

largely guided, by special instincts in the aid which they give to the

members of the same community; but they are likewise in part

impelled by mutual love and sympathy, assisted apparently by some

amount of reason. Although man, as just remarked, has no special

instincts to tell him how to aid his fellow-men, he still has the

impulse, and with his improved intellectual faculties would

naturally be much guided in this respect by reason and experience.

Instinctive sympathy would also cause him to value highly the

approbation of his fellows; for, as Mr. Bain has clearly shewn,* the

love of praise and the strong feeling of glory, and the still stronger

horror of scorn and infamy, "are due to the workings of sympathy."

Consequently man would be influenced in the highest degree by the

wishes, approbation, and blame of his fellow-men, as expressed by

their gestures and language. Thus the social instincts, which must

have been acquired by man in a very rude state, and probably even by

his early ape-like progenitors, still give the impulse to some of

his best actions; but his actions are in a higher degree determined by

the expressed wishes and judgment of his fellow-men, and unfortunately

very often by his own strong selfish desires. But as love, sympathy

and self-command become strengthened by habit, and as the power of

reasoning becomes clearer, so that man can value justly the

judgments of his fellows, he will feel himself impelled, apart from

any transitory pleasure or pain, to certain lines of conduct. He might

then declare- not that any barbarian or uncultivated man could thus

think- I am the supreme judge of my own conduct, and in the words of

Kant, I will not in my own person violate the dignity of humanity.



  * Mental and Moral Science, 1868, p. 254.



  The more enduring Social Instincts conquer the less persistent

Instincts.- We have not, however, as yet considered the main point, on

which, from our present point of view, the whole question of the moral

sense turns. Why should a man feel that he ought to obey one

instinctive desire rather than another? Why is he bitterly

regretful, if he has yielded to a strong sense of self-preservation,

and has not risked his life to save that of a fellow-creature? Or

why does he regret having stolen food from hunger?

  It is evident in the first place, that with mankind the

instinctive impulses have different degrees of strength; a savage will

risk his own life to save that of a member of the same community,

but will be wholly indifferent about a stranger: a young and timid

mother urged by the maternal instinct will, without a moment's

hesitation, run the greatest danger for her own infant, but not for

a mere fellow-creature. Nevertheless many a civilized man, or even

boy, who never before risked his life for another, but full of courage

and sympathy, has disregarded the instinct of self-preservation, and

plunged at once into a torrent to save a drowning man, though a

stranger. In this case man is impelled by the same instinctive motive,

which made the heroic little American monkey, formerly described, save

his keeper, by attacking the great and dreaded baboon. Such actions as

the above appear to be the simple result of the greater strength of

the social or maternal instincts rather than that of any other

instinct or motive; for they are performed too instantaneously for

reflection, or for pleasure or pain to be felt at the time; though, if

prevented by any cause, distress or even misery might be felt. In a

timid man, on the other hand, the instinct of self-preservation, might

be so strong, that he would be unable to force himself to run any such

risk, perhaps not even for his own child.

  I am aware that some persons maintain that actions performed

impulsively, as in the above cases, do not come under the dominion

of the moral sense, and cannot be called moral. They confine this term

to actions done deliberately, after a victory over opposing desires,

or when prompted by some exalted motive. But it appears scarcely

possible to draw any clear line of distinction of this kind.* As far

as exalted motives are concerned, many instances have been recorded of

savages, destitute of any feeling of general benevolence towards

mankind, and not guided by any religious motive, who have deliberately

sacrificed their lives as prisoners,*(2) rather than betray their

comrades; and surely their conduct ought to be considered as moral. As

far as deliberation, and the victory over opposing motives are

concerned, animals may be seen doubting between opposed instincts,

in rescuing their offspring or comrades from danger; yet their

actions, though done for the good of others, are not called moral.

Moreover, anything performed very often by us, will at last be done

without deliberation or hesitation, and can then hardly be

distinguished from an instinct; yet surely no one will pretend that

such an action ceases to be moral. On the contrary, we all feel that

an act cannot be considered as perfect, or as performed in the most

noble manner, unless it be done impulsively, without deliberation or

effort, in the same manner as by a man in whom the requisite qualities

are innate. He who is forced to overcome his fear or want of

sympathy before he acts, deserves, however, in one way higher credit

than the man whose innate disposition leads him to a good act

without effort. As we cannot distinguish between motives, we rank

all actions of a certain class as moral, if performed by a moral

being. A moral being is one who is capable of comparing his past and

future actions or motives, and of approving or disapproving of them.

We have no reason to suppose that any of the lower animals have this

capacity; therefore, when a Newfoundland dog drags a child out of

the water, or a monkey faces danger to rescue its comrade, or takes

charge of an orphan monkey, we do not call its conduct moral. But in

the case of man, who alone can with certainty be ranked as a moral

being, actions of a certain class are called moral, whether

performed deliberately, after a struggle with opposing motives, or

impulsively through instinct, or from the effects of slowly-gained

habit.



  * I refer here to the distinction between what has been called

material and formal morality. I am glad to find that Professor

Huxley (Critiques and Addresses, 1873, p. 287) takes the same view

on this subject as I do. Mr. Leslie Stephen remarks (Essays on Free

Thinking and Plain Speaking, 1873, p. 83), "The metaphysical

distinction between material and formal morality is as irrelevant as

other such distinctions."

  *(2) I have given one such case, namely of three Patagonian

Indians who preferred being shot, one after the other, to betraying

the plans of their companions in war (Journal of Researches, 1845,

p. 103).



  But to return to our more immediate subject. Although some instincts

are more powerful than others, and thus lead to corresponding actions,

yet it is untenable, that in man the social instincts (including the

love of praise and fear of blame) possess greater strength, or have,

through long habit, acquired greater strength than the instincts of

self-preservation, hunger, lust, vengeance, &c. Why then does man

regret, even though trying to banish such regret, that he has followed

the one natural impulse rather than the other; and why does he further

feel that he ought to regret his conduct? Man in this respect

differs profoundly from the lower animals. Nevertheless we can, I

think, see with some degree of clearness the reason of this

difference.

  Man, from the activity of his mental faculties, cannot avoid

reflection: past impressions and images are incessantly and clearly

passing through his mind. Now with those animals which live

permanently in a body, the social instincts are ever present and

persistent. Such animals are always ready to utter the

danger-signal, to defend the community, and to give aid to their

fellows in accordance with their habits; they feel at all times,

without the stimulus of any special passion or desire, some degree

of love and sympathy for them; they are unhappy if long separated from

them, and always happy to be again in their company. So it is with

ourselves. Even when we are quite alone, how often do we think with

pleasure or pain of what others think of us,- of their imagined

approbation or disapprobation; and this all follows from sympathy, a

fundamental element of the social instincts. A man who possessed no

trace of such instincts would be an unnatural monster. On the other

hand, the desire to satisfy hunger, or any passion such as

vengeance, is in its nature temporary, and can for a time be fully

satisfied. Nor is it easy, perhaps hardly possible, to call up with

complete vividness the feeling, for instance, of hunger; nor indeed,

as has often been remarked, of any suffering. The instinct of

self-preservation is not felt except in the presence of danger; and

many a coward has thought himself brave until he has met his enemy

face to face. The wish for another man's property is perhaps as

persistent a desire as any that can be named; but even in this case

the satisfaction of actual possession is generally a weaker feeling

than the desire: many a thief, if not an habitual one, after success

has wondered why he stole some article.*



  * Enmity or hatred seems also to be a highly persistent feeling,

perhaps more so than any other that can be named. Envy is defined as

hatred of another for some excellence or success; and Bacon insists

(Essay ix.), "Of all other affections envy is the most importune and

continual." Dogs are very apt to hate both strange men and strange

dogs, especially if they live near at hand, but do not belong to the

same family, tribe, or clan; this feeling would thus seem to be

innate, and is certainly a most persistent one. It seems to be the

complement and converse of the true social instinct. From what we hear

of savages, it would appear that something of the same kind holds good

with them. If this be so, it would be a small step in any one to

transfer such feelings to any member of the same tribe if he had

done him an injury and had become his enemy. Nor is it probable that

the primitive conscience would reproach a man for injuring his

enemy; rather it would reproach him, if he had not revenged himself.

To do good in return for evil, to love your enemy, is a height of

morality to which it may be doubted whether the social instincts

would, by themselves, have ever led us. It is necessary that these

instincts, together with sympathy, should have been highly

cultivated and extended by the aid of reason, instruction, and the

love or fear of God, before any such golden rule would ever be thought

of and obeyed.



  A man cannot prevent past impressions often repassing through his

mind; he will thus be driven to make a comparison between the

impressions of past hunger, vengeance satisfied, or danger shunned

at other men's cost, with the almost ever-present instinct of

sympathy, and with his early knowledge of what others consider as

praiseworthy or blameable. This knowledge cannot be banished from

his mind, and from instinctive sympathy is esteemed of great moment.

He will then feel as if he had been baulked in following a present

instinct or habit, and this with all animals causes dissatisfaction,

or even misery.

  The above case of the swallow affords an illustration, though of a

reversed nature, of a temporary though for the time strongly

persistent instinct conquering another instinct, which is usually

dominant over all others. At the proper season these birds seem all

day long to be impressed with the desire to migrate; their habits

change; they become restless, are noisy and congregate in flocks.

Whilst the mother-bird is feeding, or brooding over her nestlings, the

maternal instinct is probably stronger than the migratory; but the

instinct which is the more persistent gains the victory, and at

last, at a moment when her young ones are not in sight, she takes

flight and deserts them. When arrived at the end of her long

journey, and the migratory instinct has ceased to act, what an agony

of remorse the bird would feel, if, from being endowed with great

mental activity, she could not prevent the image constantly passing

through her mind, of her young ones perishing in the bleak north

from cold and hunger.

  At the moment of action, man will no doubt be apt to follow the

stronger impulse; and though this may occasionally prompt him to the

noblest deeds, it will more commonly lead him to gratify his own

desires at the expense of other men. But after their gratification

when past and weaker impressions are judged by the ever-enduring

social instinct, and by his deep regard for the good opinion of his

fellows, retribution will surely come. He will then feel remorse,

repentance, regret, or shame; this latter feeling, however, relates

almost exclusively to the judgment of others. He will consequently

resolve more or less firmly to act differently for the future; and

this is conscience; for conscience looks backwards, and serves as a

guide for the future.

  The nature and strength of the feelings which we call regret, shame,

repentance or remorse, depend apparently not only on the strength of

the violated instinct, but partly on the strength of the temptation,

and often still more on the judgment of our fellows. How far each

man values the appreciation of others, depends on the strength of

his innate or acquired feeling of sympathy; and on his own capacity

for reasoning out the remote consequences of his acts. Another element

is most important, although not necessary, the reverence or fear of

the Gods, or Spirits believed in by each man: and this applies

especially in cases of remorse. Several critics have objected that

though some slight regret or repentance may be explained by the view

advocated in this chapter, it is impossible thus to account for the

soul-shaking feeling of remorse. But I can see little force in this

objection. My critics do not define what they mean by remorse, and I

can find no definition implying more than an overwhelming sense of

repentance. Remorse seems to bear the same relation to repentance,

as rage does to anger, or agony to pain. It is far from strange that

an instinct so strong and so generally admired, as maternal love,

should, if disobeyed, lead to the deepest misery, as soon as the

impression of the past cause of disobedience is weakened. Even when an

action is opposed to no special instinct, merely to know that our

friends and equals despise us for it is enough to cause great

misery. Who can doubt that the refusal to fight a duel through fear

has caused many men an agony of shame? Many a Hindoo, it is said,

has been stirred to the bottom of his soul by having partaken of

unclean food. Here is another case of what must, I think, be called

remorse. Dr. Landor acted as a magistrate in West Australia, and

relates* that a native on his farm, after losing one of his wives from

disease, came and said that, "He was going to a distant tribe to spear

a woman, to satisfy his sense of duty to his wife. I told him that

if he did so, I would send him to prison for life. He remained about

the farm for some months, but got exceedingly thin, and complained

that he could not rest or eat, that his wife's spirit was haunting

him, because he had not taken a life for hers. I was inexorable, and

assured him that nothing should save him if he did." Nevertheless

the man disappeared for more than a year, and then returned in high

condition; and his other wife told Dr. Landor that her husband had

taken the life of a woman belonging to a distant tribe; but it was

impossible to obtain legal evidence of the act. The breach of a rule

held sacred by the tribe, will thus, as it seems, give rise to the

deepest feelings,- and this quite apart from the social instincts,

excepting in so far as the rule is grounded on the judgment of the

community. How so many strange superstitions have arisen throughout

the world we know not; nor can we tell how some real and great crimes,

such as incest, have come to be held in an abhorrence (which is not

however quite universal) by the lowest savages. It is even doubtful

whether in some tribes incest would be looked on with greater

horror, than would the marriage of a man with a woman bearing the same

name, though not a relation. "To violate this law is a crime which the

Australians hold in the greatest abhorrence, in this agreeing

exactly with certain tribes of North America. When the question is put

in either district, is it worse to kill a girl of a foreign tribe,

or to marry a girl of one's own, an answer just opposite to ours would

be given without hesitation."*(2) We may, therefore, reject the

belief, lately insisted on by some writers, that the abhorrence of

incest is due to our possessing a special God-implanted conscience. On

the whole it is intelligible, that a man urged by so powerful a

sentiment as remorse, though arising as above explained, should be led

to act in a manner, which he has been taught to believe serves as an

expiation, such as delivering himself up to justice.



  * Insanity in Relation to Law, Ontario, United States, 1871, p. 1.

  *(2) E. B. Tylor, in Contemporary Review, April, 1873, p. 707.



  Man prompted by his conscience, will through long habit acquire such

perfect self-command, that his desires and passions will at last yield

instantly and without a struggle to his social sympathies and

instincts, including his feeling for the judgment of his fellows.

The still hungry, or the still revengeful man will not think of

stealing food, or of wreaking his vengeance. It is possible, or as

we shall hereafter see, even probable, that the habit of

self-command may, like other habits, be inherited. Thus at last man

comes to feel, through aequired and perhaps inherited habit, that it

is best for him to obey his more persistent impulses. The imperious

word ought seems merely to imply the consciousness of the existence of

a rule of conduct, however it may have originated. Formerly it must

have been often vehemently urged that an insulted gentleman ought to

fight a duel. We even say that a pointer ought to point, and a

retriever to retrieve game. If they fail to do so, they fail in

their duty and act wrongly.

  If any desire or instinct leading to an action opposed to the good

of others still appears, when recalled to mind, as strong as, or

stronger than, the social instinct, a man will feel no keen regret

at having followed it; but he will be conscious that if his conduct

were known to his fellows, it would meet with their disapprobation;

and few are so destitute of sympathy as not to feel discomfort when

this is realised. If he has no such sympathy, and if his desires

leading to bad actions are at the time strong, and when recalled are

not over-mastered by the persistent social instincts, and the judgment

of others, then he is essentially a bad man;* and the sole restraining

motive left is the fear of punishment, and the conviction that in

the long run it would be best for his own selfish interests to

regard the good of others rather than his own.



  * Dr. Prosper Despine, in his Psychologie Naturelle, 1868 (tom.

i., p. 243; tom. ii., p. 169) gives many curious cases of the worst

criminals who apparently have been entirely destitute of conscience.



  It is obvious that every one may with an easy conscience gratify his

own desires, if they do not interfere with his social instincts,

that is with the good of others; but in order to be quite free from

self-reproach, or at least of anxiety, it is almost necessary for

him to avoid the disapprobation, whether reasonable or not, of his

fellow-men. Nor must he break through the fixed habits of his life,

especially if these are supported by reason; for if he does, he will

assuredly feel dissatisfaction. He must likewise avoid the reprobation

of the one God or gods in whom. according to his knowledge or

superstition, he may believe; but in this case the additional fear

of divine punishment often supervenes.

  The strictly Social Virtues at first alone regarded.- The above view

of the origin and nature of the moral sense, which tells us what we

ought to do, and of the conscience which reproves us if we disobey it,

accords well with what we see of the early and undeveloped condition

of this faculty in mankind. The virtues which must be practised, at

least generally, by rude men, so that they may associate in a body,

are those which are still recognised as the most important. But they

are practised almost exclusively in relation to the men of the same

tribe; and their opposites are not regarded as crimes in relation to

the men of other tribes. No tribe could hold together if murder,

robbery, treachery, &c., were common; consequently such crimes

within the limits of the same tribe "are branded with everlasting

infamy";* but excite no such sentiment beyond these limits. A

North-American Indian is well pleased with himself, and is honoured by

others, when he scalps a man of another tribe; and a Dyak cuts off the

head of an unoffending person, and dries it as a trophy. The murder of

infants has prevailed on the largest scale throughout the world,*(2)

and has met with no reproach; but infanticide, especially of

females, has been thought to be good for the tribe, or at least not

injurious. Suicide during former times was not generally considered as

a crime,*(3) but rather, from the courage displayed, as an

honourable act; and it is still practised by some semi-civilised and

savage nations without reproach, for it does not obviously concern

others of the tribe. It has been recorded that an Indian Thug

conscientiously regretted that he had not robbed and strangled as many

travellers as did his father before him. In a rude state of

civilisation the robbery of strangers is, indeed, generally considered

as honourable.



  * See an able article in the North British Review, 1867, p. 395. See

also Mr. W. Bagehot's articles on the "Importance of Obedience and

Coherence to Primitive Man, " in the Fortnightly Review, 1867, p. 529,

and 1868, p. 457, &c.

  *(2) The fullest account which I have met with is by Dr. Gerland, in

his Ober den Aussterben der Naturvolker, 1868: but I shall have to

recur to the subject of infanticide in a future chapter.

  *(3) See the very interesting discussion on suicide in Lecky's

History of European Morals, vol. i., 1869, p. 223. With respect to

savages, Mr. Winwood Reade informs me that the negroes of west

Africa often commit suicide. It is well known how common it was

amongst the miserable aborigines of South America after the Spanish

conquest. For New Zealand, see The Voyage of the Novara, and for the

Aleutian Islands, Muller, as quoted by Houzeau, Les Facultes Mentales,

&c., tom. ii., p. 136.



  Slavery, although in some ways beneficial during ancient times,*

is a great crime; yet it was not so regarded until quite recently,

even by the most civilised nations. And this was especially the

case, because the slaves belonged in general to a race different

from that of their masters. As barbarians do not regard the opinion of

their women, wives are commonly treated like slaves. Most savages

are utterly indifferent to the sufferings of strangers, or even

delight in witnessing them. It is well known that the women and

children of the North American Indians aided in torturing their

enemies. Some savages take a horrid pleasure in cruelty to

animals,*(2) and humanity is an unknown virtue. Nevertheless,

besides the family affections, kindness is common, especially during

sickness, between the members of the same tribe, and is sometimes

extended beyond these limits. Mungo Park's touching account of the

kindness of the negro women of the interior to him is well known. Many

instances could be given of the noble fidelity of savages towards each

other, but not to strangers; common experience justifies the maxim

of the Spaniard, "Never, never trust an Indian." There cannot be

fidelity without truth; and this fundamental virtue is not rare

between the members of the same tribe: thus Mungo Park heard the negro

women teaching their young children to love the truth. This, again, is

one of the virtues which becomes so deeply rooted in the mind, that it

is sometimes practised by savages, even at a high cost, towards

strangers; but to lie to your enemy has rarely been thought a sin,

as the history of modern diplomacy too plainly shews. As soon as a

tribe has a recognised leader, disobedience becomes a crime, and

even abject submission is looked at as a sacred virtue.



  * See Mr. Bagehot, Physics and Politics, 1872, p. 72.

  *(2) See, for instance, Mr. Hamilton's account of the Kaffirs,

Anthropological Review, 1870, p. xv.



  As during rude times no man can be useful or faithful to his tribe

without courage, this quality has universally been placed in the

highest rank; and although in civilised countries a good yet timid man

may be far more useful to the community than a brave one, we cannot

help instinctively honouring the latter above a coward, however

benevolent. Prudence, on the other hand, which does not concern the

welfare of others, though a very useful virtue, has never been

highly esteemed. As no man can practise the virtues necessary for

the welfare of his tribe without self-sacrifice, self-command, and the

power of endurance, these qualities have been at all times highly

and most justly valued. The American savage voluntarily submits to the

most horrid tortures without a groan, to prove and strengthen his

fortitude and courage; and we cannot help admiring him, or even an

Indian Fakir, who, from a foolish religious motive, swings suspended

by a hook buried in his flesh.

  The other so-called self-regarding virtues, which do not

obviously, though they may really, affect the welfare of the tribe,

have never been esteemed by savages, though now highly appreciated

by civilised nations. The greatest intemperance is no reproach with

savages. Utter licentiousness, and unnatural crimes, prevail to an

astounding extent.* As soon, however, as marriage, whether polygamous,

or monogamous, becomes common, jealousy will lead to the inculcation

of female virtue; and this, being honoured, will tend to spread to the

unmarried females. How slowly it spreads to the male sex, we see at

the present day. Chastity eminently requires self-command;

therefore, it has been honoured from a very early period in the

moral history of civilised man. As a consequence of this, the

senseless practice of celibacy has been ranked from a remote period as

a virtue.*(2) The hatred of indecency, which appears to us so

natural as to be thought innate, and which is so valuable an aid to

chastity, is a modern virtue, appertaining exclusively, as Sir G.

Staunton remarks,*(3) to civilised life. This is shewn by the

ancient religious rites of various nations, by the drawings on the

walls of Pompeii, and by the practices of many savages.



  * Mr. M'Lennan has given (Primitive Marriage, 1865, p. 176) a good

collection of facts on this head.

  *(2) Lecky, History of European Morals, vol. i., 1869, p. 109.

  *(3) Embassy to China, vol. ii., p. 348.



  We have now seen that actions are regarded by savages, and were

probably so regarded by primeval man, as good or bad, solely as they

obviously affect the welfare of the tribe,- not that of the species,

nor that of an individual member of the tribe. This conclusion

agrees well with the belief that the so-called moral sense is

aboriginally derived from the social instincts, for both relate at

first exclusively to the community.

  The chief causes of the low morality of savages, as judged by our

standard, are, firstly, the confinement of sympathy to the same tribe.

Secondly, powers of reasoning insufficient to recognise the bearing of

many virtues, especially of the self-regarding virtues, on the general

welfare of the tribe. Savages, for instance, fail to trace the

multiplied evils consequent on a want of temperance, chastity, &c.

And, thirdly, weak power of self-command; for this power has not

been strengthened through long-continued, perhaps inherited, habit,

instruction and religion.

  I have entered into the above details on the immorality of savages,*

because some authors have recently taken a high view of their moral

nature, or have attributed most of their crimes to mistaken

benevolence.*(2) These authors appear to rest their conclusion on

savages possessing those virtues which are serviceable, or even

necessary, for the existence of the family and of the tribe,-

qualities which they undoubtedly do possess, and often in a high

degree.



  * See on this subject copious evidence in chap. vii. of Sir J.

Lubbock, Origin of Civilisation, 1870.

  *(2) For instance Lecky, History of European Morals, vol. i., p.

124.



  Concluding Remarks.- It was assumed formerly by philosophers of

the derivative* school of morals that the foundation of morality lay

in a form of Selfishness; but more recently the "Greatest happiness

principle" has been brought prominently forward. It is, however,

more correct to speak of the latter principle as the standard, and not

as the motive of conduct. Nevertheless, all the authors whose works

I have consulted, with a few exceptions,*(2) write as if there must be

a distinct motive for every action, and that this must be associated

with some pleasure or displeasure. But man seems often to act

impulsively, that is from instinct or long habit, without any

consciousness of pleasure, in the same manner as does probably a bee

or ant, when it blindly follows its instincts. Under circumstances

of extreme peril, as during a fire, when a man endeavours to save a

fellow-creature without a moment's hesitation, he can hardly feel

pleasure; and still less has he time to reflect on the dissatisfaction

which he might subsequently experience if he did not make the attempt.

Should he afterwards reflect over his own conduct, he would feel

that there lies within him an impulsive power widely different from

a search after pleasure or happiness; and this seems to be the

deeply planted social instinct.



  * This term is used in an able article in the Westminster Review,

Oct., 1869, p. 498; For the "Greatest happiness principle," see J.

S. Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 448.

  *(2) Mill recognises (System of Logic, vol. ii., p. 422) in the

clearest manner, that actions may be performed through habit without

the anticipation of pleasure. Mr. H. Sidgwick also, in his "Essay on

Pleasure and Desire" (The Contemporary Review, April, 1872, p. 671),

remarks: "To sum up, in contravention of the doctrine that our

conscious active impulses are always directed towards the production

of agreeable sensations in ourselves, I would maintain that we find

everywhere in consciousness extra-regarding impulse, directed

towards something that is not pleasure; that in many case the

impulse is so far incompatible with the self-regarding that the two do

not easily co-exist in the same moment of consciousness." A dim

feeling that our impulses do not by any means always arise from any

contemporaneous or anticipated pleasure, has, I cannot but think, been

one chief cause of the acceptance of the intuitive theory of morality,

and of the rejection of the utilitarian or "Greatest happiness"

theory. With respect to the latter theory the standard and the

motive of conduct have no doubt often been confused, but they are

really in some degree blended.



  In the case of the lower animals it seems much more appropriate to

speak of their social instincts, as having been developed for the

general good rather than for the general happiness of the species. The

term, general good, may be defined as the rearing of the greatest

number of individuals in full vigour and health, with all their

faculties perfect, under the conditions to which they are subjected.

As the social instincts both of man and the lower animals have no

doubt been developed by nearly the same steps, it would be

advisable, if found practicable, to use the same definition in both

cases, and to take as the standard of morality, the general good or

welfare of the community, rather than the general happiness; but

this definition would perhaps require some limitation on account of

political ethics.

  When a man risks his life to save that of a fellow-creature, it

seems also more correct to say that he acts for the general good,

rather than for the general happiness of mankind. No doubt the welfare

and the happiness of the individual usually coincide; and a contented,

happy tribe will flourish better than one that is discontented and

unhappy. We have seen that even at an early period in the history of

man, the expressed wishes of the community will have naturally

influenced to a large extent the conduct of each member; and as all

wish for happiness, the "greatest happiness principle" will have

become a most important secondary guide and object; the social

instinct, however, together with sympathy (which leads to our

regarding the approbation and disapprobation of others), having served

as the primary impulse and guide. Thus the reproach is removed of

laying the foundation of the noblest part of our nature in the base

principle of selfishness; unless, indeed, the satisfaction which every

animal feels, when it follows its proper instincts, and the

dissatisfaction felt when prevented, be called selfish.

  The wishes and opinions of the members of the same community,

expressed at first orally, but later by writing also, either form

the sole guides of our conduct, or greatly reinforce the social

instincts; such opinions, however, have sometimes a tendency

directly opposed to these instincts. This latter fact is well

exemplified by the Law of Honour, that is, the law of the opinion of

our equals, and not of all our countrymen. The breach of this law,

even when the breach is known to be strictly accordant with true

morality, has caused many a man more agony than a real crime. We

recognise the same influence in the burning sense of shame which

most of us have felt, even after the interval of years, when calling

to mind some accidental breach of a trifling, though fixed, rule of

etiquette. The judgment of the community will generally be guided by

some rude experience of what is best in the long run for all the

members; but this judgment will not rarely err from ignorance and weak

powers of reasoning. Hence the strangest customs and superstitions, in

complete opposition to the true welfare and happiness of mankind, have

become all-powerful throughout the world. We see this in the horror

felt by a Hindoo who breaks his caste, and in many other such cases.

It would be difficult to distinguish between the remorse felt by a

Hindoo who has yielded to the temptation of eating unclean food,

from that felt after committing a theft; but the former would probably

be the more severe.

  How so many absurd rules of conduct, as well as so many absurd

religious beliefs, have originated, we do not know; nor how it is that

they have become, in all quarters of the world, so deeply impressed on

the mind of men; but it is worthy of remark that a belief constantly

inculcated during the early years of life, whilst the brain is

impressible, appears to acquire almost the nature of an instinct;

and the very essence of an instinct is that it is followed

independently of reason. Neither can we say why certain admirable

virtues, such as the love of truth, are much more highly appreciated

by some savage tribes than by others;* nor, again, why similar

differences prevail even amongst highly civilised nations. Knowing how

firmly fixed many strange customs and superstitions have become, we

need feel no surprise that the self-regarding virtues, supported as

they are by reason, should now appear to us so natural as to be

thought innate, although they were not valued by man in his early

condition.



  * Good instances are given by Mr. Wallace in Scientific Opinion,

Sept. 15, 1869; and more fully in his Contributions to the Theory of

Natural Selection, 1870, p. 353.



  Not withstanding many sources of doubt, man can generally and

readily distinguish between the higher and lower moral rules. The

higher are founded on the social instincts, and relate to the

welfare of others. They are supported by the approbation of our

fellow-men and by reason. The lower rules, though some of them when

implying self-sacrifice hardly deserve to be called lower, relate

chiefly to self, and arise from public opinion, matured by

experience and cultivation; for they are not practised by rude tribes.

  As man advances in civilisation, and small tribes are united into

larger communities, the simplest reason would tell each individual

that he ought to extend his social instincts and sympathies to all the

members of the same nation, though personally unknown to him. This

point being once reached, there is only an artificial barrier to

prevent his sympathies extending to the men of all nations and

races. If, indeed, such men are separated from him by great

differences in appearance or habits, experience unfortunately shews us

how long it is, before we look at them as our fellow-creatures.

Sympathy beyond the confines of man, that is, humanity to the lower

animals, seems to be one of the latest moral acquisitions. It is

apparently unfelt by savages, except towards their pets. How little

the old Romans knew of it is shewn by their abhorrent gladiatorial

exhibitions. The very idea of humanity, as far as I could observe, was

new to most of the Gauchos of the Pampas. This virtue, one of the

noblest with which man is endowed, seems to arise incidentally from

our sympathies becoming more tender and more widely diffused, until

they are extended to all sentient beings. As soon as this virtue is

honoured and practised by some few men, it spreads through instruction

and example to the young, and eventually becomes incorporated in

public opinion.

  The highest possible stage in moral culture is when we recognise

that we ought to control our thoughts, and "not even in inmost thought

to think again the sins that made the past so pleasant to us."*

Whatever makes any bad action familiar to the mind, renders its

performance by so much the easier. As Marcus Aurelius long ago said,

"Such as are thy habitual thoughts, such also will be the character of

thy mind; for the soul is dyed by the thoughts."*(2)



  * Tennyson, Idylls of the King, p. 244.

  *(2) Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, Bk. V, sect. 16.



  Our great philosopher, Herbert Spencer, has recently explained his

views on the moral sense. He says, "I believe that the experiences

of utility organised and consolidated through all past generations

of the human race, have been producing corresponding modifications,

which, by continued transmission and accumulation, have become in us

certain faculties of moral intuition- certain emotions responding to

right and wrong conduct, which have no apparent basis in the

individual experiences of utility."* There is not the least inherent

improbability, as it seems to me, in virtuous tendencies being more or

less strongly inherited; for, not to mention the various

dispositions and habits transmitted by many of our domestic animals to

their offspring, I have heard of authentic cases in which a desire

to steal and a tendency to lie appeared to run in families of the

upper ranks; and as stealing is a rare crime in the wealthy classes,

we can hardly account by accidental coincidence for the tendency

occurring in two or three members of the same family. If bad

tendencies are transmitted, it is probable that good ones are likewise

transmitted. That the state of the body by affecting the brain, has

great influence on the moral tendencies is known to most of those

who have suffered from chronic derangements of the digestion or liver.

The same fact is likewise shewn by the "perversion or destruction of

the moral sense being often one of the earliest symptoms of mental

derangement";*(2) and insanity is notoriously often inherited.

Except through the principle of the transmission of moral

tendencies, we cannot understand the differences believed to exist

in this respect between the various races of mankind.



  * Letter to Mr. Mill in Bain's Mental and Moral Science, 1868, p.

722.

  *(2) Maudsley, Body and Mind, 1870, p. 60.



  Even the partial transmission of virtuous tendencies would be an

immense assistance to the primary impulse derived directly and

indirectly from the social instincts. Admitting for a moment that

virtuous tendencies are inherited, it appears probable, at least in

such cases as chastity, temperance, humanity to animals, &c., that

they become first impressed on the mental organization through

habit, instruction and example, continued during several generations

in the same family, and in a quite subordinate degree, or not at

all, by the individuals possessing such virtues having succeeded

best in the struggle for life. My chief source of doubt with respect

to any such inheritance, is that senseless customs, superstitions, and

tastes, such as the horror of a Hindoo for unclean food, ought on

the same principle to be transmitted. I have not met with any evidence

in support of the transmission of superstitious customs or senseless

habits, although in itself it is perhaps not less probable than that

animals should acquire inherited tastes for certain kinds of food or

fear of certain foes.



  Finally the social instincts, which no doubt were acquired by man as

by the lower animals for the good of the community, will from the

first have given to him some wish to aid his fellows, some feeling

of sympathy, and have compelled him to regard their approbation and

disapprobation. Such impulses will have served him at a very early

period as a rude rule of right and wrong. But as man gradually

advanced in intellectual power, and was enabled to trace the more

remote consequences of his actions; as he aequired sufficient

knowledge to reject baneful customs and superstitions; as he

regarded more and more, not only the welfare, but the happiness of his

fellow-men; as from habit, following on beneficial experience,

instruction and example, his sympathies became more tender and

widely diffused, extending to men of all races, to the imbecile,

maimed, and other useless members of society, and finally to the lower

animals,- so would the standard of his morality rise higher and

higher. And it is admitted by moralists of the derivative school and

by some intuitionists, that the standard of morality has risen since

an early period in the history of man.*



  * A writer in the North British Review (July, 1869, p. 531), well

capable of forming a sound judgment, expresses himself strongly in

favour of this conclusion. Mr. Lecky (History of Morals, vol. i., p.

143) seems to a certain extent to coincide therein.



  As a struggle may sometimes be seen going on between the various

instincts of the lower animals, it is not surprising that there should

be a struggle in man between his social instincts, with their

derived virtues, and his lower, though momentarily stronger impulses

or desires. This, as Mr. Galton* has remarked, is all the less

surprising, as man has emerged from a state of barbarism within a

comparatively recent period. After having yielded to some temptation

we feel a sense of dissatisfaction, shame, repentance, or remorse,

analogous to the feelings caused by other powerful instincts or

desires, when left unsatisfied or baulked. We compare the weakened

impression of a past temptation with the ever present social

instincts, or with habits, gained in early youth and strengthened

during our whole lives, until they have become almost as strong as

instincts. If with the temptation still before us we do not yield,

it is because either the social instinct or some custom is at the

moment predominant, or because we have learnt that it will appear to

us hereafter the stronger, when compared with the weakened

impression of the temptation, and we realise that its violation

would cause us suffering. Looking to future generations, there is no

cause to fear that the social instincts will grow weaker, and we may

expect that virtuous habits will grow stronger, becoming perhaps fixed

by inheritance. In this case the struggle between our higher and lower

impulses will be less severe, and virtue will be triumphant.



  * See his remarkable work on Hereditary Genius, 1869, p. 349. The

Duke of Argyll (Primeval Man, 1869, p. 188) has some good remarks on

the contest in man's nature between right and wrong.



  Summary of the last two Chapters.- There can be no doubt that the

difference between the mind of the lowest man and that of the

highest animal is immense. An anthropomorphous ape, if he could take a

dispassionate view of his own case, would admit that though he could

form an artful plan to plunder a garden- though he could use stones

for fighting or for breaking open nuts, yet that the thought of

fashioning a stone into a tool was quite beyond his scope. Still less,

as he would admit, could he follow out a train of metaphysical

reasoning, or solve a mathematical problem, or reflect on God, or

admire a grand natural scene. Some apes, however, would probably

declare that they could and did admire the beauty of the coloured skin

and fur of their partners in marriage. They would admit, that though

they could make other apes understand by cries some of their

perceptions and simpler wants, the notion of expressing definite ideas

by definite sounds had never crossed their minds. They might insist

that they were ready to aid their fellow-apes of the same troop in

many ways, to risk their lives for them, and to take charge of their

orphans; but they would be forced to acknowledge that disinterested

love for all living creatures, the most noble attribute of man, was

quite beyond their comprehension.

  Nevertheless the difference in mind between man and the higher

animals, great as it is, certainly is one of degree and not of kind.

We have seen that the senses and intuitions, the various emotions

and faculties, such as love, memory, attention, curiosity,

imitation, reason, &c., of which man boasts, may be found in an

incipient, or even sometimes in a well-developed condition, in the

lower animals. They are also capable of some inherited improvement, as

we see in the domestic dog compared with the wolf or jackal. If it

could be proved that certain high mental powers, such as the formation

of general concepts, self-consciousness, &c., were absolutely peculiar

to man, which seems extremely doubtful, it is not improbable that

these qualities are merely the incidental results of other

highly-advanced intellectual faculties; and these again mainly the

result of the continued use of a perfect language. At what age does

the new-born infant possess the power of abstraction, or become

self-conscious, and reflect on its own existence? We cannot answer;

nor can we answer in regard to the ascending organic scale. The

half-art, half-instinct of language still bears the stamp of its

gradual evolution. The ennobling belief in God is not universal with

man; and the belief in spiritual agencies naturally follows from other

mental powers. The moral sense perhaps affords the best and highest

distinction between man and the lower animals; but I need say

nothing on this head, as I have so lately endeavoured to shew that the

social instincts,- the prime principle of man's moral constitution*

- with the aid of active intellectual powers and the effects of habit,

naturally lead to the golden rule, "As ye would that men should do

to you, do ye to them likewise"; and this lies at the foundation of

morality.



  * Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, Bk. V, sect. 55.



  In the next chapter I shall make some few remarks on the probable

steps and means by which the several mental and moral faculties of man

have been gradually evolved. That such evolution is at least possible,

ought not to be denied, for we daily see these faculties developing in

every infant; and we may trace a perfect gradation from the mind of an

utter idiot, lower than that of an animal low in the scale, to the

mind of a Newton.




Search the Secular Web | Bookstore | What's new? | Add an URL | Send Feedback | Disclaimer

[Internet Infidels] [Freethought Ring] [Church-State Ring]  [Free Speech Online]

Copyright © Internet Infidels 1995-1997. All rights reserved.

Last updated: Friday, 30-Jan-98 10:45:15 MST