POLITICS

by Aristotle

Translated by Benjamin Jowett

Book Three

Part I

He who would inquire into the essence and attributes of various kinds of governments must first of all determine 'What is a state?' Atpresent this is a disputed question. Some say that the state has done a certain act; others, no, not the state, but the oligarchy or thetyrant. And the legislator or statesman is concerned entirely with the state; a constitution or government being an arrangement of theinhabitants of a state. But a state is composite, like any other whole made up of many parts; these are the citizens, who compose it.It is evident, therefore, that we must begin by asking, Who is the citizen, and what is the meaning of the term? For here again theremay be a difference of opinion. He who is a citizen in a democracy will often not be a citizen in an oligarchy. Leaving out ofconsideration those who have been made citizens, or who have obtained the name of citizen any other accidental manner, we maysay, first, that a citizen is not a citizen because he lives in a certain place, for resident aliens and slaves share in the place; nor is hea citizen who has no legal right except that of suing and being sued; for this right may be enjoyed under the provisions of a treaty.Nay, resident aliens in many places do not possess even such rights completely, for they are obliged to have a patron, so that theydo but imperfectly participate in citizenship, and we call them citizens only in a qualified sense, as we might apply the term tochildren who are too young to be on the register, or to old men who have been relieved from state duties. Of these we do not sayquite simply that they are citizens, but add in the one case that they are not of age, and in the other, that they are past the age, orsomething of that sort; the precise expression is immaterial, for our meaning is clear. Similar difficulties to those which I havementioned may be raised and answered about deprived citizens and about exiles. But the citizen whom we are seeking to define isa citizen in the strictest sense, against whom no such exception can be taken, and his special characteristic is that he shares in theadministration of justice, and in offices. Now of offices some are discontinuous, and the same persons are not allowed to hold themtwice, or can only hold them after a fixed interval; others have no limit of time- for example, the office of a dicast or ecclesiast. It may,indeed, be argued that these are not magistrates at all, and that their functions give them no share in the government. But surely it isridiculous to say that those who have the power do not govern. Let us not dwell further upon this, which is a purely verbal question;what we want is a common term including both dicast and ecclesiast. Let us, for the sake of distinction, call it 'indefinite office,' andwe will assume that those who share in such office are citizens. This is the most comprehensive definition of a citizen, and best suitsall those who are generally so called.

But we must not forget that things of which the underlying principles differ in kind, one of them being first, another second, anotherthird, have, when regarded in this relation, nothing, or hardly anything, worth mentioning in common. Now we see that governmentsdiffer in kind, and that some of them are prior and that others are posterior; those which are faulty or perverted are necessarilyposterior to those which are perfect. (What we mean by perversion will be hereafter explained.) The citizen then of necessity differsunder each form of government; and our definition is best adapted to the citizen of a democracy; but not necessarily to other states.For in some states the people are not acknowledged, nor have they any regular assembly, but only extraordinary ones; and suits aredistributed by sections among the magistrates. At Lacedaemon, for instance, the Ephors determine suits about contracts, which theydistribute among themselves, while the elders are judges of homicide, and other causes are decided by other magistrates. A similarprinciple prevails at Carthage; there certain magistrates decide all causes. We may, indeed, modify our definition of the citizen soas to include these states. In them it is the holder of a definite, not of an indefinite office, who legislates and judges, and to some orall such holders of definite offices is reserved the right of deliberating or judging about some things or about all things. Theconception of the citizen now begins to clear up.

He who has the power to take part in the deliberative or judicial administration of any state is said by us to be a citizens of that state;and, speaking generally, a state is a body of citizens sufficing for the purposes of life.

Part II

But in practice a citizen is defined to be one of whom both the parents are citizens; others insist on going further back; say to two orthree or more ancestors. This is a short and practical definition but there are some who raise the further question: How this third orfourth ancestor came to be a citizen? Gorgias of Leontini, partly because he was in a difficulty, partly in irony, said- 'Mortars are whatis made by the mortar-makers, and the citizens of Larissa are those who are made by the magistrates; for it is their trade to makeLarissaeans.' Yet the question is really simple, for, if according to the definition just given they shared in the government, they werecitizens. This is a better definition than the other. For the words, 'born of a father or mother who is a citizen,' cannot possibly apply tothe first inhabitants or founders of a state.

There is a greater difficulty in the case of those who have been made citizens after a revolution, as by Cleisthenes at Athens after theexpulsion of the tyrants, for he enrolled in tribes many metics, both strangers and slaves. The doubt in these cases is, not who is, butwhether he who is ought to be a citizen; and there will still be a furthering the state, whether a certain act is or is not an act of thestate; for what ought not to be is what is false. Now, there are some who hold office, and yet ought not to hold office, whom wedescribe as ruling, but ruling unjustly. And the citizen was defined by the fact of his holding some kind of rule or office- he who holds ajudicial or legislative office fulfills our definition of a citizen. It is evident, therefore, that the citizens about whom the doubt has arisenmust be called citizens.

Part III

Whether they ought to be so or not is a question which is bound up with the previous inquiry. For a parallel question is raisedrespecting the state, whether a certain act is or is not an act of the state; for example, in the transition from an oligarchy or a tyrannyto a democracy. In such cases persons refuse to fulfill their contracts or any other obligations, on the ground that the tyrant, and notthe state, contracted them; they argue that some constitutions are established by force, and not for the sake of the common good.But this would apply equally to democracies, for they too may be founded on violence, and then the acts of the democracy will beneither more nor less acts of the state in question than those of an oligarchy or of a tyranny. This question runs up into another: onwhat principle shall we ever say that the state is the same, or different? It would be a very superficial view which considered only theplace and the inhabitants (for the soil and the population may be separated, and some of the inhabitants may live in one place andsome in another). This, however, is not a very serious difficulty; we need only remark that the word 'state' is ambiguous.

It is further asked: When are men, living in the same place, to be regarded as a single city- what is the limit? Certainly not the wall ofthe city, for you might surround all Peloponnesus with a wall. Like this, we may say, is Babylon, and every city that has the compassof a nation rather than a city; Babylon, they say, had been taken for three days before some part of the inhabitants became aware ofthe fact. This difficulty may, however, with advantage be deferred to another occasion; the statesman has to consider the size of thestate, and whether it should consist of more than one nation or not.

Again, shall we say that while the race of inhabitants, as well as their place of abode, remain the same, the city is also the same,although the citizens are always dying and being born, as we call rivers and fountains the same, although the water is always flowingaway and coming again Or shall we say that the generations of men, like the rivers, are the same, but that the state changes? For,since the state is a partnership, and is a partnership of citizens in a constitution, when the form of government changes, andbecomes different, then it may be supposed that the state is no longer the same, just as a tragic differs from a comic chorus,although the members of both may be identical. And in this manner we speak of every union or composition of elements as differentwhen the form of their composition alters; for example, a scale containing the same sounds is said to be different, accordingly as theDorian or the Phrygian mode is employed. And if this is true it is evident that the sameness of the state consists chiefly in thesameness of the constitution, and it may be called or not called by the same name, whether the inhabitants are the same or entirelydifferent. It is quite another question, whether a state ought or ought not to fulfill engagements when the form of government changes.

Part IV

There is a point nearly allied to the preceding: Whether the virtue of a good man and a good citizen is the same or not. But, beforeentering on this discussion, we must certainly first obtain some general notion of the virtue of the citizen. Like the sailor, the citizen isa member of a community. Now, sailors have different functions, for one of them is a rower, another a pilot, and a third a look-outman, a fourth is described by some similar term; and while the precise definition of each individual's virtue applies exclusively to him,there is, at the same time, a common definition applicable to them all. For they have all of them a common object, which is safety innavigation. Similarly, one citizen differs from another, but the salvation of the community is the common business of them all. Thiscommunity is the constitution; the virtue of the citizen must therefore be relative to the constitution of which he is a member. If, then,there are many forms of government, it is evident that there is not one single virtue of the good citizen which is perfect virtue. But wesay that the good man is he who has one single virtue which is perfect virtue. Hence it is evident that the good citizen need not ofnecessity possess the virtue which makes a good man.

The same question may also be approached by another road, from a consideration of the best constitution. If the state cannot beentirely composed of good men, and yet each citizen is expected to do his own business well, and must therefore have virtue, stillinasmuch as all the citizens cannot be alike, the virtue of the citizen and of the good man cannot coincide. All must have the virtue ofthe good citizen- thus, and thus only, can the state be perfect; but they will not have the virtue of a good man, unless we assume thatin the good state all the citizens must be good.

Again, the state, as composed of unlikes, may be compared to the living being: as the first elements into which a living being isresolved are soul and body, as soul is made up of rational principle and appetite, the family of husband and wife, property of masterand slave, so of all these, as well as other dissimilar elements, the state is composed; and, therefore, the virtue of all the citizenscannot possibly be the same, any more than the excellence of the leader of a chorus is the same as that of the performer who standsby his side. I have said enough to show why the two kinds of virtue cannot be absolutely and always the same.

But will there then be no case in which the virtue of the good citizen and the virtue of the good man coincide? To this we answer thatthe good ruler is a good and wise man, and that he who would be a statesman must be a wise man. And some persons say thateven the education of the ruler should be of a special kind; for are not the children of kings instructed in riding and military exercises?As Euripides says:

"No subtle arts for me, but what the state requires. "

As though there were a special education needed by a ruler. If then the virtue of a good ruler is the same as that of a good man, andwe assume further that the subject is a citizen as well as the ruler, the virtue of the good citizen and the virtue of the good man cannotbe absolutely the same, although in some cases they may; for the virtue of a ruler differs from that of a citizen. It was the sense of thisdifference which made Jason say that 'he felt hungry when he was not a tyrant,' meaning that he could not endure to live in a privatestation. But, on the other hand, it may be argued that men are praised for knowing both how to rule and how to obey, and he is saidto be a citizen of approved virtue who is able to do both. Now if we suppose the virtue of a good man to be that which rules, and thevirtue of the citizen to include ruling and obeying, it cannot be said that they are equally worthy of praise. Since, then, it is sometimesthought that the ruler and the ruled must learn different things and not the same, but that the citizen must know and share in them both,the inference is obvious. There is, indeed, the rule of a master, which is concerned with menial offices- the master need not knowhow to perform these, but may employ others in the execution of them: the other would be degrading; and by the other I mean thepower actually to do menial duties, which vary much in character and are executed by various classes of slaves, such, for example,as handicraftsmen, who, as their name signifies, live by the labor of their hands: under these the mechanic is included. Hence inancient times, and among some nations, the working classes had no share in the government- a privilege which they only acquiredunder the extreme democracy. Certainly the good man and the statesman and the good citizen ought not to learn the crafts ofinferiors except for their own occasional use; if they habitually practice them, there will cease to be a distinction between master andslave.

This is not the rule of which we are speaking; but there is a rule of another kind, which is exercised over freemen and equals by birth-a constitutional rule, which the ruler must learn by obeying, as he would learn the duties of a general of cavalry by being under theorders of a general of cavalry, or the duties of a general of infantry by being under the orders of a general of infantry, and by havinghad the command of a regiment and of a company. It has been well said that 'he who has never learned to obey cannot be a goodcommander.' The two are not the same, but the good citizen ought to be capable of both; he should know how to govern like afreeman, and how to obey like a freeman- these are the virtues of a citizen. And, although the temperance and justice of a ruler aredistinct from those of a subject, the virtue of a good man will include both; for the virtue of the good man who is free and also asubject, e.g., his justice, will not be one but will comprise distinct kinds, the one qualifying him to rule, the other to obey, and differingas the temperance and courage of men and women differ. For a man would be thought a coward if he had no more courage than acourageous woman, and a woman would be thought loquacious if she imposed no more restraint on her conversation than the goodman; and indeed their part in the management of the household is different, for the duty of the one is to acquire, and of the other topreserve. Practical wisdom only is characteristic of the ruler: it would seem that all other virtues must equally belong to ruler andsubject. The virtue of the subject is certainly not wisdom, but only true opinion; he may be compared to the maker of the flute, whilehis master is like the flute-player or user of the flute.

From these considerations may be gathered the answer to the question, whether the virtue of the good man is the same as that ofthe good citizen, or different, and how far the same, and how far different.

Part V

There still remains one more question about the citizen: Is he only a true citizen who has a share of office, or is the mechanic to beincluded? If they who hold no office are to be deemed citizens, not every citizen can have this virtue of ruling and obeying; for thisman is a citizen And if none of the lower class are citizens, in which part of the state are they to be placed? For they are not residentaliens, and they are not foreigners. May we not reply, that as far as this objection goes there is no more absurdity in excluding themthan in excluding slaves and freedmen from any of the above-mentioned classes? It must be admitted that we cannot consider allthose to be citizens who are necessary to the existence of the state; for example, children are not citizen equally with grown-up men,who are citizens absolutely, but children, not being grown up, are only citizens on a certain assumption. Nay, in ancient times, andamong some nations the artisan class were slaves or foreigners, and therefore the majority of them are so now. The best form ofstate will not admit them to citizenship; but if they are admitted, then our definition of the virtue of a citizen will not apply to everycitizen nor to every free man as such, but only to those who are freed from necessary services. The necessary people are eitherslaves who minister to the wants of individuals, or mechanics and laborers who are the servants of the community. These reflectionscarried a little further will explain their position; and indeed what has been said already is of itself, when understood, explanationenough.

Since there are many forms of government there must be many varieties of citizen and especially of citizens who are subjects; sothat under some governments the mechanic and the laborer will be citizens, but not in others, as, for example, in aristocracy or theso-called government of the best (if there be such an one), in which honors are given according to virtue and merit; for no man canpractice virtue who is living the life of a mechanic or laborer. In oligarchies the qualification for office is high, and therefore no laborercan ever be a citizen; but a mechanic may, for an actual majority of them are rich. At Thebes there was a law that no man could holdoffice who had not retired from business for ten years. But in many states the law goes to the length of admitting aliens; for in somedemocracies a man is a citizen though his mother only be a citizen; and a similar principle is applied to illegitimate children; the lawis relaxed when there is a dearth of population. But when the number of citizens increases, first the children of a male or a femaleslave are excluded; then those whose mothers only are citizens; and at last the right of citizenship is confined to those whose fathersand mothers are both citizens.

Hence, as is evident, there are different kinds of citizens; and he is a citizen in the highest sense who shares in the honors of thestate. Compare Homer's words, 'like some dishonored stranger'; he who is excluded from the honors of the state is no better than analien. But when his exclusion is concealed, then the object is that the privileged class may deceive their fellow inhabitants.

As to the question whether the virtue of the good man is the same as that of the good citizen, the considerations already adducedprove that in some states the good man and the good citizen are the same, and in others different. When they are the same it is notevery citizen who is a good man, but only the statesman and those who have or may have, alone or in conjunction with others, theconduct of public affairs.

Part VI

Having determined these questions, we have next to consider whether there is only one form of government or many, and if many,what they are, and how many, and what are the differences between them.

A constitution is the arrangement of magistracies in a state, especially of the highest of all. The government is everywhere sovereignin the state, and the constitution is in fact the government. For example, in democracies the people are supreme, but in oligarchies,the few; and, therefore, we say that these two forms of government also are different: and so in other cases.

First, let us consider what is the purpose of a state, and how many forms of government there are by which human society isregulated. We have already said, in the first part of this treatise, when discussing household management and the rule of a master,that man is by nature a political animal. And therefore, men, even when they do not require one another's help, desire to live together;not but that they are also brought together by their common interests in proportion as they severally attain to any measure ofwell-being. This is certainly the chief end, both of individuals and of states. And also for the sake of mere life (in which there ispossibly some noble element so long as the evils of existence do not greatly overbalance the good) mankind meet together andmaintain the political community. And we all see that men cling to life even at the cost of enduring great misfortune, seeming to find inlife a natural sweetness and happiness.

There is no difficulty in distinguishing the various kinds of authority; they have been often defined already in discussions outside theschool. The rule of a master, although the slave by nature and the master by nature have in reality the same interests, is neverthelessexercised primarily with a view to the interest of the master, but accidentally considers the slave, since, if the slave perish, the rule ofthe master perishes with him. On the other hand, the government of a wife and children and of a household, which we have calledhousehold management, is exercised in the first instance for the good of the governed or for the common good of both parties, butessentially for the good of the governed, as we see to be the case in medicine, gymnastic, and the arts in general, which are onlyaccidentally concerned with the good of the artists themselves. For there is no reason why the trainer may not sometimes practicegymnastics, and the helmsman is always one of the crew. The trainer or the helmsman considers the good of those committed to hiscare. But, when he is one of the persons taken care of, he accidentally participates in the advantage, for the helmsman is also asailor, and the trainer becomes one of those in training. And so in politics: when the state is framed upon the principle of equality andlikeness, the citizens think that they ought to hold office by turns. Formerly, as is natural, every one would take his turn of service; andthen again, somebody else would look after his interest, just as he, while in office, had looked after theirs. But nowadays, for the sakeof the advantage which is to be gained from the public revenues and from office, men want to be always in office. One might imaginethat the rulers, being sickly, were only kept in health while they continued in office; in that case we may be sure that they would behunting after places. The conclusion is evident: that governments which have a regard to the common interest are constituted inaccordance with strict principles of justice, and are therefore true forms; but those which regard only the interest of the rulers are alldefective and perverted forms, for they are despotic, whereas a state is a community of freemen.

Part VII

Having determined these points, we have next to consider how many forms of government there are, and what they are; and in thefirst place what are the true forms, for when they are determined the perversions of them will at once be apparent. The wordsconstitution and government have the same meaning, and the government, which is the supreme authority in states, must be in thehands of one, or of a few, or of the many. The true forms of government, therefore, are those in which the one, or the few, or the many,govern with a view to the common interest; but governments which rule with a view to the private interest, whether of the one or of thefew, or of the many, are perversions. For the members of a state, if they are truly citizens, ought to participate in its advantages. Offorms of government in which one rules, we call that which regards the common interests, kingship or royalty; that in which more thanone, but not many, rule, aristocracy; and it is so called, either because the rulers are the best men, or because they have at heart thebest interests of the state and of the citizens. But when the citizens at large administer the state for the common interest, thegovernment is called by the generic name- a constitution. And there is a reason for this use of language. One man or a few mayexcel in virtue; but as the number increases it becomes more difficult for them to attain perfection in every kind of virtue, though theymay in military virtue, for this is found in the masses. Hence in a constitutional government the fighting-men have the supreme power,and those who possess arms are the citizens.

Of the above-mentioned forms, the perversions are as follows: of royalty, tyranny; of aristocracy, oligarchy; of constitutionalgovernment, democracy. For tyranny is a kind of monarchy which has in view the interest of the monarch only; oligarchy has in viewthe interest of the wealthy; democracy, of the needy: none of them the common good of all.

Part VIII

But there are difficulties about these forms of government, and it will therefore be necessary to state a little more at length the natureof each of them. For he who would make a philosophical study of the various sciences, and does not regard practice only, ought notto overlook or omit anything, but to set forth the truth in every particular. Tyranny, as I was saying, is monarchy exercising the rule of amaster over the political society; oligarchy is when men of property have the government in their hands; democracy, the opposite,when the indigent, and not the men of property, are the rulers. And here arises the first of our difficulties, and it relates to thedistinction drawn. For democracy is said to be the government of the many. But what if the many are men of property and have thepower in their hands? In like manner oligarchy is said to be the government of the few; but what if the poor are fewer than the rich,and have the power in their hands because they are stronger? In these cases the distinction which we have drawn between thesedifferent forms of government would no longer hold good.

Suppose, once more, that we add wealth to the few and poverty to the many, and name the governments accordingly- an oligarchy issaid to be that in which the few and the wealthy, and a democracy that in which the many and the poor are the rulers- there will still bea difficulty. For, if the only forms of government are the ones already mentioned, how shall we describe those other governments alsojust mentioned by us, in which the rich are the more numerous and the poor are the fewer, and both govern in their respective states?

The argument seems to show that, whether in oligarchies or in democracies, the number of the governing body, whether the greaternumber, as in a democracy, or the smaller number, as in an oligarchy, is an accident due to the fact that the rich everywhere are few,and the poor numerous. But if so, there is a misapprehension of the causes of the difference between them. For the real differencebetween democracy and oligarchy is poverty and wealth. Wherever men rule by reason of their wealth, whether they be few or many,that is an oligarchy, and where the poor rule, that is a democracy. But as a fact the rich are few and the poor many; for few arewell-to-do, whereas freedom is enjoyed by an, and wealth and freedom are the grounds on which the oligarchical and democraticalparties respectively claim power in the state.

Part IX

Let us begin by considering the common definitions of oligarchy and democracy, and what is justice oligarchical and democratical.For all men cling to justice of some kind, but their conceptions are imperfect and they do not express the whole idea. For example,justice is thought by them to be, and is, equality, not. however, for however, for but only for equals. And inequality is thought to be, andis, justice; neither is this for all, but only for unequals. When the persons are omitted, then men judge erroneously. The reason is thatthey are passing judgment on themselves, and most people are bad judges in their own case. And whereas justice implies a relationto persons as well as to things, and a just distribution, as I have already said in the Ethics, implies the same ratio between thepersons and between the things, they agree about the equality of the things, but dispute about the equality of the persons, chiefly forthe reason which I have just given- because they are bad judges in their own affairs; and secondly, because both the parties to theargument are speaking of a limited and partial justice, but imagine themselves to be speaking of absolute justice. For the one party,if they are unequal in one respect, for example wealth, consider themselves to be unequal in all; and the other party, if they are equalin one respect, for example free birth, consider themselves to be equal in all. But they leave out the capital point. For if men met andassociated out of regard to wealth only, their share in the state would be proportioned to their property, and the oligarchical doctrinewould then seem to carry the day. It would not be just that he who paid one mina should have the same share of a hundred minae,whether of the principal or of the profits, as he who paid the remaining ninety-nine. But a state exists for the sake of a good life, andnot for the sake of life only: if life only were the object, slaves and brute animals might form a state, but they cannot, for they have noshare in happiness or in a life of free choice. Nor does a state exist for the sake of alliance and security from injustice, nor yet for thesake of exchange and mutual intercourse; for then the Tyrrhenians and the Carthaginians, and all who have commercial treaties withone another, would be the citizens of one state. True, they have agreements about imports, and engagements that they will do nowrong to one another, and written articles of alliance. But there are no magistrates common to the contracting parties who willenforce their engagements; different states have each their own magistracies. Nor does one state take care that the citizens of theother are such as they ought to be, nor see that those who come under the terms of the treaty do no wrong or wickedness at an, butonly that they do no injustice to one another. Whereas, those who care for good government take into consideration virtue and vice instates. Whence it may be further inferred that virtue must be the care of a state which is truly so called, and not merely enjoys thename: for without this end the community becomes a mere alliance which differs only in place from alliances of which the memberslive apart; and law is only a convention, 'a surety to one another of justice,' as the sophist Lycophron says, and has no real power tomake the citizens

This is obvious; for suppose distinct places, such as Corinth and Megara, to be brought together so that their walls touched, still theywould not be one city, not even if the citizens had the right to intermarry, which is one of the rights peculiarly characteristic of states.Again, if men dwelt at a distance from one another, but not so far off as to have no intercourse, and there were laws among them thatthey should not wrong each other in their exchanges, neither would this be a state. Let us suppose that one man is a carpenter,another a husbandman, another a shoemaker, and so on, and that their number is ten thousand: nevertheless, if they have nothing incommon but exchange, alliance, and the like, that would not constitute a state. Why is this? Surely not because they are at a distancefrom one another: for even supposing that such a community were to meet in one place, but that each man had a house of his own,which was in a manner his state, and that they made alliance with one another, but only against evil-doers; still an accurate thinkerwould not deem this to be a state, if their intercourse with one another was of the same character after as before their union. It isclear then that a state is not a mere society, having a common place, established for the prevention of mutual crime and for the sakeof exchange. These are conditions without which a state cannot exist; but all of them together do not constitute a state, which is acommunity of families and aggregations of families in well-being, for the sake of a perfect and self-sufficing life. Such a communitycan only be established among those who live in the same place and intermarry. Hence arise in cities family connections,brotherhoods, common sacrifices, amusements which draw men together. But these are created by friendship, for the will to livetogether is friendship. The end of the state is the good life, and these are the means towards it. And the state is the union of familiesand villages in a perfect and self-sufficing life, by which we mean a happy and honorable life.

Our conclusion, then, is that political society exists for the sake of noble actions, and not of mere companionship. Hence they whocontribute most to such a society have a greater share in it than those who have the same or a greater freedom or nobility of birth butare inferior to them in political virtue; or than those who exceed them in wealth but are surpassed by them in virtue.

From what has been said it will be clearly seen that all the partisans of different forms of government speak of a part of justice only.

Part X

There is also a doubt as to what is to be the supreme power in the state: Is it the multitude? Or the wealthy? Or the good? Or the onebest man? Or a tyrant? Any of these alternatives seems to involve disagreeable consequences. If the poor, for example, becausethey are more in number, divide among themselves the property of the rich- is not this unjust? No, by heaven (will be the reply), for thesupreme authority justly willed it. But if this is not injustice, pray what is? Again, when in the first division all has been taken, and themajority divide anew the property of the minority, is it not evident, if this goes on, that they will ruin the state? Yet surely, virtue is notthe ruin of those who possess her, nor is justice destructive of a state; and therefore this law of confiscation clearly cannot be just. If itwere, all the acts of a tyrant must of necessity be just; for he only coerces other men by superior power, just as the multitude coercethe rich. But is it just then that the few and the wealthy should be the rulers? And what if they, in like manner, rob and plunder thepeople- is this just? if so, the other case will likewise be just. But there can be no doubt that all these things are wrong and unjust.

Then ought the good to rule and have supreme power? But in that case everybody else, being excluded from power, will bedishonored. For the offices of a state are posts of honor; and if one set of men always holds them, the rest must be deprived of them.Then will it be well that the one best man should rule? Nay, that is still more oligarchical, for the number of those who are dishonoredis thereby increased. Some one may say that it is bad in any case for a man, subject as he is to all the accidents of human passion,to have the supreme power, rather than the law. But what if the law itself be democratical or oligarchical, how will that help us out ofour difficulties? Not at all; the same consequences will follow.

Part XI

Most of these questions may be reserved for another occasion. The principle that the multitude ought to be supreme rather than thefew best is one that is maintained, and, though not free from difficulty, yet seems to contain an element of truth. For the many, ofwhom each individual is but an ordinary person, when they meet together may very likely be better than the few good, if regarded notindividually but collectively, just as a feast to which many contribute is better than a dinner provided out of a single purse. For eachindividual among the many has a share of virtue and prudence, and when they meet together, they become in a manner one man,who has many feet, and hands, and senses; that is a figure of their mind and disposition. Hence the many are better judges than asingle man of music and poetry; for some understand one part, and some another, and among them they understand the whole.There is a similar combination of qualities in good men, who differ from any individual of the many, as the beautiful are said to differfrom those who are not beautiful, and works of art from realities, because in them the scattered elements are combined, although, iftaken separately, the eye of one person or some other feature in another person would be fairer than in the picture. Whether thisprinciple can apply to every democracy, and to all bodies of men, is not clear. Or rather, by heaven, in some cases it is impossible ofapplication; for the argument would equally hold about brutes; and wherein, it will be asked, do some men differ from brutes? Butthere may be bodies of men about whom our statement is nevertheless true. And if so, the difficulty which has been already raised,and also another which is akin to it -viz., what power should be assigned to the mass of freemen and citizens, who are not rich andhave no personal merit- are both solved. There is still a danger in aflowing them to share the great offices of state, for their folly willlead them into error, and their dishonesty into crime. But there is a danger also in not letting them share, for a state in which manypoor men are excluded from office will necessarily be full of enemies. The only way of escape is to assign to them some deliberativeand judicial functions. For this reason Solon and certain other legislators give them the power of electing to offices, and of calling themagistrates to account, but they do not allow them to hold office singly. When they meet together their perceptions are quite goodenough, and combined with the better class they are useful to the state (just as impure food when mixed with what is pure sometimesmakes the entire mass more wholesome than a small quantity of the pure would be), but each individual, left to himself, forms animperfect judgment. On the other hand, the popular form of government involves certain difficulties. In the first place, it might beobjected that he who can judge of the healing of a sick man would be one who could himself heal his disease, and make him whole-that is, in other words, the physician; and so in all professions and arts. As, then, the physician ought to be called to account byphysicians, so ought men in general to be called to account by their peers. But physicians are of three kinds: there is the ordinarypractitioner, and there is the physician of the higher class, and thirdly the intelligent man who has studied the art: in all arts there issuch a class; and we attribute the power of judging to them quite as much as to professors of the art. Secondly, does not the sameprinciple apply to elections? For a right election can only be made by those who have knowledge; those who know geometry, forexample, will choose a geometrician rightly, and those who know how to steer, a pilot; and, even if there be some occupations andarts in which private persons share in the ability to choose, they certainly cannot choose better than those who know. So that,according to this argument, neither the election of magistrates, nor the calling of them to account, should be entrusted to the many.Yet possibly these objections are to a great extent met by our old answer, that if the people are not utterly degraded, althoughindividually they may be worse judges than those who have special knowledge- as a body they are as good or better. Moreover,there are some arts whose products are not judged of solely, or best, by the artists themselves, namely those arts whose productsare recognized even by those who do not possess the art; for example, the knowledge of the house is not limited to the builder only;the user, or, in other words, the master, of the house will be even a better judge than the builder, just as the pilot will judge better of arudder than the carpenter, and the guest will judge better of a feast than the cook.

This difficulty seems now to be sufficiently answered, but there is another akin to it. That inferior persons should have authority ingreater matters than the good would appear to be a strange thing, yet the election and calling to account of the magistrates is thegreatest of all. And these, as I was saying, are functions which in some states are assigned to the people, for the assembly issupreme in all such matters. Yet persons of any age, and having but a small property qualification, sit in the assembly and deliberateand judge, although for the great officers of state, such as treasurers and generals, a high qualification is required. This difficulty maybe solved in the same manner as the preceding, and the present practice of democracies may be really defensible. For the powerdoes not reside in the dicast, or senator, or ecclesiast, but in the court, and the senate, and the assembly, of which individualsenators, or ecclesiasts, or dicasts, are only parts or members. And for this reason the many may claim to have a higher authoritythan the few; for the people, and the senate, and the courts consist of many persons, and their property collectively is greater than theproperty of one or of a few individuals holding great offices. But enough of this.

The discussion of the first question shows nothing so clearly as that laws, when good, should be supreme; and that the magistrate ormagistrates should regulate those matters only on which the laws are unable to speak with precision owing to the difficulty of anygeneral principle embracing all particulars. But what are good laws has not yet been clearly explained; the old difficulty remains. Thegoodness or badness, justice or injustice, of laws varies of necessity with the constitutions of states. This, however, is clear, that thelaws must be adapted to the constitutions. But if so, true forms of government will of necessity have just laws, and perverted forms ofgovernment will have unjust laws.

Part XII

In all sciences and arts the end is a good, and the greatest good and in the highest degree a good in the most authoritative of all-this is the political science of which the good is justice, in other words, the common interest. All men think justice to be a sort ofequality; and to a certain extent they agree in the philosophical distinctions which have been laid down by us about Ethics. For theyadmit that justice is a thing and has a relation to persons, and that equals ought to have equality. But there still remains a question:equality or inequality of what? Here is a difficulty which calls for political speculation. For very likely some persons will say that officesof state ought to be unequally distributed according to superior excellence, in whatever respect, of the citizen, although there is noother difference between him and the rest of the community; for that those who differ in any one respect have different rights andclaims. But, surely, if this is true, the complexion or height of a man, or any other advantage, will be a reason for his obtaining agreater share of political rights. The error here lies upon the surface, and may be illustrated from the other arts and sciences. When anumber of flute players are equal in their art, there is no reason why those of them who are better born should have better flutes givento them; for they will not play any better on the flute, and the superior instrument should be reserved for him who is the superior artist.If what I am saying is still obscure, it will be made clearer as we proceed. For if there were a superior flute-player who was far inferiorin birth and beauty, although either of these may be a greater good than the art of flute-playing, and may excel flute-playing in agreater ratio than he excels the others in his art, still he ought to have the best flutes given to him, unless the advantages of wealthand birth contribute to excellence in flute-playing, which they do not. Moreover, upon this principle any good may be compared withany other. For if a given height may be measured wealth and against freedom, height in general may be so measured. Thus if Aexcels in height more than B in virtue, even if virtue in general excels height still more, all goods will be commensurable; for if acertain amount is better than some other, it is clear that some other will be equal. But since no such comparison can be made, it isevident that there is good reason why in politics men do not ground their claim to office on every sort of inequality any more than inthe arts. For if some be slow, and others swift, that is no reason why the one should have little and the others much; it is ingymnastics contests that such excellence is rewarded. Whereas the rival claims of candidates for office can only be based on thepossession of elements which enter into the composition of a state. And therefore the noble, or free-born, or rich, may with goodreason claim office; for holders of offices must be freemen and taxpayers: a state can be no more composed entirely of poor menthan entirely of slaves. But if wealth and freedom are necessary elements, justice and valor are equally so; for without the formerqualities a state cannot exist at all, without the latter not well.

Part XIII

If the existence of the state is alone to be considered, then it would seem that all, or some at least, of these claims are just; but, if wetake into account a good life, then, as I have already said, education and virtue have superior claims. As, however, those who areequal in one thing ought not to have an equal share in all, nor those who are unequal in one thing to have an unequal share in all, it iscertain that all forms of government which rest on either of these principles are perversions. All men have a claim in a certain sense,as I have already admitted, but all have not an absolute claim. The rich claim because they have a greater share in the land, and landis the common element of the state; also they are generally more trustworthy in contracts. The free claim under the same tide as thenoble; for they are nearly akin. For the noble are citizens in a truer sense than the ignoble, and good birth is always valued in a man'sown home and country. Another reason is, that those who are sprung from better ancestors are likely to be better men, for nobility isexcellence of race. Virtue, too, may be truly said to have a claim, for justice has been acknowledged by us to be a social virtue, and itimplies all others. Again, the many may urge their claim against the few; for, when taken collectively, and compared with the few, theyare stronger and richer and better. But, what if the good, the rich, the noble, and the other classes who make up a state, are all livingtogether in the same city, Will there, or will there not, be any doubt who shall rule? No doubt at all in determining who ought to rule ineach of the above-mentioned forms of government. For states are characterized by differences in their governing bodies-one ofthem has a government of the rich, another of the virtuous, and so on. But a difficulty arises when all these elements co-exist. Howare we to decide? Suppose the virtuous to be very few in number: may we consider their numbers in relation to their duties, and askwhether they are enough to administer the state, or so many as will make up a state? Objections may be urged against all theaspirants to political power. For those who found their claims on wealth or family might be thought to have no basis of justice; on thisprinciple, if any one person were richer than all the rest, it is clear that he ought to be ruler of them. In like manner he who is verydistinguished by his birth ought to have the superiority over all those who claim on the ground that they are freeborn. In an aristocracy,or government of the best, a like difficulty occurs about virtue; for if one citizen be better than the other members of the government,however good they may be, he too, upon the same principle of justice, should rule over them. And if the people are to be supremebecause they are stronger than the few, then if one man, or more than one, but not a majority, is stronger than the many, they ought torule, and not the many.

All these considerations appear to show that none of the principles on which men claim to rule and to hold all other men in subjectionto them are strictly right. To those who claim to be masters of the government on the ground of their virtue or their wealth, the manymight fairly answer that they themselves are often better and richer than the few- I do not say individually, but collectively. And anotheringenious objection which is sometimes put forward may be met in a similar manner. Some persons doubt whether the legislatorwho desires to make the justest laws ought to legislate with a view to the good of the higher classes or of the many, when the casewhich we have mentioned occurs. Now what is just or right is to be interpreted in the sense of 'what is equal'; and that which is right inthe sense of being equal is to be considered with reference to the advantage of the state, and the common good of the citizens. Anda citizen is one who shares in governing and being governed. He differs under different forms of government, but in the best state heis one who is able and willing to be governed and to govern with a view to the life of virtue.

If, however, there be some one person, or more than one, although not enough to make up the full complement of a state, whosevirtue is so pre-eminent that the virtues or the political capacity of all the rest admit of no comparison with his or theirs, he or they canbe no longer regarded as part of a state; for justice will not be done to the superior, if he is reckoned only as the equal of those whoare so far inferior to him in virtue and in political capacity. Such an one may truly be deemed a God among men. Hence we see thatlegislation is necessarily concerned only with those who are equal in birth and in capacity; and that for men of pre-eminent virtuethere is no law- they are themselves a law. Any would be ridiculous who attempted to make laws for them: they would probably retortwhat, in the fable of Antisthenes, the lions said to the hares, when in the council of the beasts the latter began haranguing andclaiming equality for all. And for this reason democratic states have instituted ostracism; equality is above all things their aim, andtherefore they ostracized and banished from the city for a time those who seemed to predominate too much through their wealth, orthe number of their friends, or through any other political influence. Mythology tells us that the Argonauts left Heracles behind for asimilar reason; the ship Argo would not take him because she feared that he would have been too much for the rest of the crew.Wherefore those who denounce tyranny and blame the counsel which Periander gave to Thrasybulus cannot be held altogether justin their censure. The story is that Periander, when the herald was sent to ask counsel of him, said nothing, but only cut off the tallestears of corn till he had brought the field to a level. The herald did not know the meaning of the action, but came and reported what hehad seen to Thrasybulus, who understood that he was to cut off the principal men in the state; and this is a policy not only expedientfor tyrants or in practice confined to them, but equally necessary in oligarchies and democracies. Ostracism is a measure of thesame kind, which acts by disabling and banishing the most prominent citizens. Great powers do the same to whole cities andnations, as the Athenians did to the Samians, Chians, and Lesbians; no sooner had they obtained a firm grasp of the empire, thanthey humbled their allies contrary to treaty; and the Persian king has repeatedly crushed the Medes, Babylonians, and other nations,when their spirit has been stirred by the recollection of their former greatness.

The problem is a universal one, and equally concerns all forms of government, true as well as false; for, although perverted forms witha view to their own interests may adopt this policy, those which seek the common interest do so likewise. The same thing may beobserved in the arts and sciences; for the painter will not allow the figure to have a foot which, however beautiful, is not in proportion,nor will the shipbuilder allow the stem or any other part of the vessel to be unduly large, any more than the chorus-master will allowany one who sings louder or better than all the rest to sing in the choir. Monarchs, too, may practice compulsion and still live inharmony with their cities, if their own government is for the interest of the state. Hence where there is an acknowledged superioritythe argument in favor of ostracism is based upon a kind of political justice. It would certainly be better that the legislator should fromthe first so order his state as to have no need of such a remedy. But if the need arises, the next best thing is that he should endeavorto correct the evil by this or some similar measure. The principle, however, has not been fairly applied in states; for, instead oflooking to the good of their own constitution, they have used ostracism for factious purposes. It is true that under perverted forms ofgovernment, and from their special point of view, such a measure is just and expedient, but it is also clear that it is not absolutely just.In the perfect state there would be great doubts about the use of it, not when applied to excess in strength, wealth, popularity, or thelike, but when used against some one who is pre-eminent in virtue- what is to be done with him? Mankind will not say that such anone is to be expelled and exiled; on the other hand, he ought not to be a subject- that would be as if mankind should claim to ruleover Zeus, dividing his offices among them. The only alternative is that all should joyfully obey such a ruler, according to what seemsto be the order of nature, and that men like him should be kings in their state for life.

Part XIV

The preceding discussion, by a natural transition, leads to the consideration of royalty, which we admit to be one of the true forms ofgovernment. Let us see whether in order to be well governed a state or country should be under the rule of a king or under someother form of government; and whether monarchy, although good for some, may not be bad for others. But first we must determinewhether there is one species of royalty or many. It is easy to see that there are many, and that the manner of government is not thesame in all of them.

Of royalties according to law, (1) the Lacedaemonian is thought to answer best to the true pattern; but there the royal power is notabsolute, except when the kings go on an expedition, and then they take the command. Matters of religion are likewise committed tothem. The kingly office is in truth a kind of generalship, irresponsible and perpetual. The king has not the power of life and death,except in a specified case, as for instance, in ancient times, he had it when upon a campaign, by right of force. This custom isdescribed in Homer. For Agamemnon is patient when he is attacked in the assembly, but when the army goes out to battle he hasthe power even of life and death. Does he not say- 'When I find a man skulking apart from the battle, nothing shall save him from thedogs and vultures, for in my hands is death'?

This, then, is one form of royalty-a generalship for life: and of such royalties some are hereditary and others elective.

(2) There is another sort of monarchy not uncommon among the barbarians, which nearly resembles tyranny. But this is both legaland hereditary. For barbarians, being more servile in character than Hellenes, and Asiadics than Europeans, do not rebel against adespotic government. Such royalties have the nature of tyrannies because the people are by nature slaves; but there is no danger oftheir being overthrown, for they are hereditary and legal. Wherefore also their guards are such as a king and not such as a tyrantwould employ, that is to say, they are composed of citizens, whereas the guards of tyrants are mercenaries. For kings rule accordingto law over voluntary subjects, but tyrants over involuntary; and the one are guarded by their fellow-citizens the others are guardedagainst them.

These are two forms of monarchy, and there was a third (3) which existed in ancient Hellas, called an Aesymnetia or dictatorship.This may be defined generally as an elective tyranny, which, like the barbarian monarchy, is legal, but differs from it in not beinghereditary. Sometimes the office was held for life, sometimes for a term of years, or until certain duties had been performed. Forexample, the Mytilenaeans elected Pittacus leader against the exiles, who were headed by Antimenides and Alcaeus the poet. AndAlcaeus himself shows in one of his banquet odes that they chose Pittacus tyrant, for he reproaches his fellow-citizens for 'havingmade the low-born Pittacus tyrant of the spiritless and ill-fated city, with one voice shouting his praises.'

These forms of government have always had the character of tyrannies, because they possess despotic power; but inasmuch asthey are elective and acquiesced in by their subjects, they are kingly.

(4) There is a fourth species of kingly rule- that of the heroic times- which was hereditary and legal, and was exercised over willingsubjects. For the first chiefs were benefactors of the people in arts or arms; they either gathered them into a community, or procuredland for them; and thus they became kings of voluntary subjects, and their power was inherited by their descendants. They took thecommand in war and presided over the sacrifices, except those which required a priest. They also decided causes either with orwithout an oath; and when they swore, the form of the oath was the stretching out of their sceptre. In ancient times their powerextended continuously to all things whatsoever, in city and country, as well as in foreign parts; but at a later date they relinquishedseveral of these privileges, and others the people took from them, until in some states nothing was left to them but the sacrifices; andwhere they retained more of the reality they had only the right of leadership in war beyond the border.

These, then, are the four kinds of royalty. First the monarchy of the heroic ages; this was exercised over voluntary subjects, butlimited to certain functions; the king was a general and a judge, and had the control of religion The second is that of the barbarians,which is a hereditary despotic government in accordance with law. A third is the power of the so-called Aesynmete or Dictator; this isan elective tyranny. The fourth is the Lacedaemonian, which is in fact a generalship, hereditary and perpetual. These four forms differfrom one another in the manner which I have described.

(5) There is a fifth form of kingly rule in which one has the disposal of all, just as each nation or each state has the disposal of publicmatters; this form corresponds to the control of a household. For as household management is the kingly rule of a house, so kinglyrule is the household management of a city, or of a nation, or of many nations.

Part XV

Of these forms we need only consider two, the Lacedaemonian and the absolute royalty; for most of the others he in a regionbetween them, having less power than the last, and more than the first. Thus the inquiry is reduced to two points: first, is itadvantageous to the state that there should be a perpetual general, and if so, should the office be confined to one family, or open tothe citizens in turn? Secondly, is it well that a single man should have the supreme power in all things? The first question falls underthe head of laws rather than of constitutions; for perpetual generalship might equally exist under any form of government, so that thismatter may be dismissed for the present. The other kind of royalty is a sort of constitution; this we have now to consider, and brieflyto run over the difficulties involved in it. We will begin by inquiring whether it is more advantageous to be ruled by the best man or bythe best laws.

The advocates of royalty maintain that the laws speak only in general terms, and cannot provide for circumstances; and that for anyscience to abide by written rules is absurd. In Egypt the physician is allowed to alter his treatment after the fourth day, but if sooner,he takes the risk. Hence it is clear that a government acting according to written laws is plainly not the best. Yet surely the rulercannot dispense with the general principle which exists in law; and this is a better ruler which is free from passion than that in which itis innate. Whereas the law is passionless, passion must ever sway the heart of man. Yes, it may be replied, but then on the otherhand an individual will be better able to deliberate in particular cases.

The best man, then, must legislate, and laws must be passed, but these laws will have no authority when they miss the mark, thoughin all other cases retaining their authority. But when the law cannot determine a point at all, or not well, should the one best man orshould all decide? According to our present practice assemblies meet, sit in judgment, deliberate, and decide, and their judgmentsan relate to individual cases. Now any member of the assembly, taken separately, is certainly inferior to the wise man. But the stateis made up of many individuals. And as a feast to which all the guests contribute is better than a banquet furnished by a single man,so a multitude is a better judge of many things than any individual.

Again, the many are more incorruptible than the few; they are like the greater quantity of water which is less easily corrupted than alittle. The individual is liable to be overcome by anger or by some other passion, and then his judgment is necessarily perverted; butit is hardly to be supposed that a great number of persons would all get into a passion and go wrong at the same moment. Let usassume that they are the freemen, and that they never act in violation of the law, but fill up the gaps which the law is obliged to leave.Or, if such virtue is scarcely attainable by the multitude, we need only suppose that the majority are good men and good citizens, andask which will be the more incorruptible, the one good ruler, or the many who are all good? Will not the many? But, you will say, theremay be parties among them, whereas the one man is not divided against himself. To which we may answer that their character is asgood as his. If we call the rule of many men, who are all of them good, aristocracy, and the rule of one man royalty, then aristocracywill be better for states than royalty, whether the government is supported by force or not, provided only that a number of men equal invirtue can be found.

The first governments were kingships, probably for this reason, because of old, when cities were small, men of eminent virtue werefew. Further, they were made kings because they were benefactors, and benefits can only be bestowed by good men. But whenmany persons equal in merit arose, no longer enduring the pre-eminence of one, they desired to have a commonwealth, and set up aconstitution. The ruling class soon deteriorated and enriched themselves out of the public treasury; riches became the path to honor,and so oligarchies naturally grew up. These passed into tyrannies and tyrannies into democracies; for love of gain in the rulingclasses was always tending to diminish their number, and so to strengthen the masses, who in the end set upon their masters andestablished democracies. Since cities have increased in size, no other form of government appears to be any longer even easy toestablish.

Even supposing the principle to be maintained that kingly power is the best thing for states, how about the family of the king? Are hischildren to succeed him? If they are no better than anybody else, that will be mischievous. But, says the lover of royalty, the king,though he might, will not hand on his power to his children. That, however, is hardly to be expected, and is too much to ask of humannature. There is also a difficulty about the force which he is to employ; should a king have guards about him by whose aid he may beable to coerce the refractory? If not, how will he administer his kingdom? Even if he be the lawful sovereign who does nothingarbitrarily or contrary to law, still he must have some force wherewith to maintain the law. In the case of a limited monarchy there isnot much difficulty in answering this question; the king must have such force as will be more than a match for one or more individuals,but not so great as that of the people. The ancients observe this principle when they have guards to any one whom they appointeddictator or tyrant. Thus, when Dionysius asked the Syracusans to allow him guards, somebody advised that they should give him onlysuch a number.

Part XVI

At this place in the discussion there impends the inquiry respecting the king who acts solely according to his own will he has now tobe considered. The so-called limited monarchy, or kingship according to law, as I have already remarked, is not a distinct form ofgovernment, for under all governments, as, for example, in a democracy or aristocracy, there may be a general holding office for life,and one person is often made supreme over the administration of a state. A magistracy of this kind exists at Epidamnus, and also atOpus, but in the latter city has a more limited power. Now, absolute monarchy, or the arbitrary rule of a sovereign over an the citizens,in a city which consists of equals, is thought by some to be quite contrary to nature; it is argued that those who are by nature equalsmust have the same natural right and worth, and that for unequals to have an equal share, or for equals to have an uneven share, inthe offices of state, is as bad as for different bodily constitutions to have the same food and clothing. Wherefore it is thought to bejust that among equals every one be ruled as well as rule, and therefore that an should have their turn. We thus arrive at law; for anorder of succession implies law. And the rule of the law, it is argued, is preferable to that of any individual. On the same principle,even if it be better for certain individuals to govern, they should be made only guardians and ministers of the law. For magistratesthere must be- this is admitted; but then men say that to give authority to any one man when all are equal is unjust. Nay, there mayindeed be cases which the law seems unable to determine, but in such cases can a man? Nay, it will be replied, the law trainsofficers for this express purpose, and appoints them to determine matters which are left undecided by it, to the best of theirjudgment. Further, it permits them to make any amendment of the existing laws which experience suggests. Therefore he who bidsthe law rule may be deemed to bid God and Reason alone rule, but he who bids man rule adds an element of the beast; for desire isa wild beast, and passion perverts the minds of rulers, even when they are the best of men. The law is reason unaffected by desire.We are told that a patient should call in a physician; he will not get better if he is doctored out of a book. But the parallel of the arts isclearly not in point; for the physician does nothing contrary to rule from motives of friendship; he only cures a patient and takes a fee;whereas magistrates do many things from spite and partiality. And, indeed, if a man suspected the physician of being in league withhis enemies to destroy him for a bribe, he would rather have recourse to the book. But certainly physicians, when they are sick, call inother physicians, and training-masters, when they are in training, other training-masters, as if they could not judge judge truly abouttheir own case and might be influenced by their feelings. Hence it is evident that in seeking for justice men seek for the mean orneutral, for the law is the mean. Again, customary laws have more weight, and relate to more important matters, than written laws,and a man may be a safer ruler than the written law, but not safer than the customary law.

Again, it is by no means easy for one man to superintend many things; he will have to appoint a number of subordinates, and whatdifference does it make whether these subordinates always existed or were appointed by him because he needed theme If, as I saidbefore, the good man has a right to rule because he is better, still two good men are better than one: this is the old saying, two goingtogether, and the prayer of Agamemnon,

"Would that I had ten such councillors! "

And at this day there are magistrates, for example judges, who have authority to decide some matters which the law is unable todetermine, since no one doubts that the law would command and decide in the best manner whatever it could. But some things can,and other things cannot, be comprehended under the law, and this is the origin of the nexted question whether the best law or thebest man should rule. For matters of detail about which men deliberate cannot be included in legislation. Nor does any one deny thatthe decision of such matters must be left to man, but it is argued that there should be many judges, and not one only. For every rulerwho has been trained by the law judges well; and it would surely seem strange that a person should see better with two eyes, or hearbetter with two ears, or act better with two hands or feet, than many with many; indeed, it is already the practice of kings to make tothemselves many eyes and ears and hands and feet. For they make colleagues of those who are the friends of themselves and theirgovernments. They must be friends of the monarch and of his government; if not his friends, they will not do what he wants; butfriendship implies likeness and equality; and, therefore, if he thinks that his friends ought to rule, he must think that those who areequal to himself and like himself ought to rule equally with himself. These are the principal controversies relating to monarchy.

Part XVII

But may not all this be true in some cases and not in others? for there is by nature both a justice and an advantage appropriate to therule of a master, another to kingly rule, another to constitutional rule; but there is none naturally appropriate to tyranny, or to any otherperverted form of government; for these come into being contrary to nature. Now, to judge at least from what has been said, it ismanifest that, where men are alike and equal, it is neither expedient nor just that one man should be lord of all, whether there arelaws, or whether there are no laws, but he himself is in the place of law. Neither should a good man be lord over good men, nor a badman over bad; nor, even if he excels in virtue, should he have a right to rule, unless in a particular case, at which I have alreadyhinted, and to which I will once more recur. But first of all, I must determine what natures are suited for government by a king, andwhat for an aristocracy, and what for a constitutional government.

A people who are by nature capable of producing a race superior in the virtue needed for political rule are fitted for kinglygovernment; and a people submitting to be ruled as freemen by men whose virtue renders them capable of political command areadapted for an aristocracy; while the people who are suited for constitutional freedom are those among whom there naturally exists awarlike multitude able to rule and to obey in turn by a law which gives office to the well-to-do according to their desert. But when awhole family or some individual, happens to be so pre-eminent in virtue as to surpass all others, then it is just that they should be theroyal family and supreme over all, or that this one citizen should be king of the whole nation. For, as I said before, to give themauthority is not only agreeable to that ground of right which the founders of all states, whether aristocratical, or oligarchical, or againdemocratical, are accustomed to put forward (for these all recognize the claim of excellence, although not the same excellence), butaccords with the principle already laid down. For surely it would not be right to kill, or ostracize, or exile such a person, or require thathe should take his turn in being governed. The whole is naturally superior to the part, and he who has this pre-eminence is in therelation of a whole to a part. But if so, the only alternative is that he should have the supreme power, and that mankind should obeyhim, not in turn, but always. These are the conclusions at which we arrive respecting royalty and its various forms, and this is theanswer to the question, whether it is or is not advantageous to states, and to which, and how.

Part XVIII

We maintain that the true forms of government are three, and that the best must be that which is administered by the best, and inwhich there is one man, or a whole family, or many persons, excelling all the others together in virtue, and both rulers and subjectsare fitted, the one to rule, the others to be ruled, in such a manner as to attain the most eligible life. We showed at the commencement of our inquiry that the virtue of the good man is necessarily the same as the virtue of the citizen of the perfect state. Clearly then in the same manner, and by the same means through which a man becomes truly good, he will frame a state that is to be ruled by an aristocracy or by a king, and the same education and the same habits will be found to make a good man and a man fit to be a statesman or a king. Having arrived at these conclusions, we must proceed to speak of the perfect state, and describe how it comes into being and is established.

Continue on to Book Four

Return to the Table of Contents
Return to List of Authors and Books