CHAPTER 1
HOW MANY KINDS OF PRINCIPALITIES THERE
ARE, AND BY WHAT MEANS THEY ARE ACQUIRED
ALL STATES, all powers, that
have held and hold rule over men have been and are either republics or
principalities. Principalities are either hereditary, in which the family
has been long established; or they are new. The new are either entirely
new, as was Milan to Francesco Sforza, or they are, as it were, members
annexed to the hereditary state of the prince who has acquired them, as
was the kingdom of Naples to that of the King of Spain. Such dominions
thus acquired are either accustomed to live under a prince, or to live
in freedom; and are acquired either by the arms of the prince himself,
or of others, or else by fortune or by ability.
CHAPTER 2
CONCERNING HEREDITARY PRINCIPALITIES
I WILL leave out all discussion on republics,
inasmuch as in another place I have written of them at length, and will
address myself only to principalities. In doing so I will keep to the order
indicated above, and discuss how such principalities are to be ruled and
preserved. I say at once there are fewer difficulties in holding hereditary
states, and those long accustomed to the family of their prince, than new
ones; for it is sufficient only not to transgress the customs of his ancestors,
and to deal prudently with circumstances as they arise, for a prince of
average powers to maintain himself in his state, unless he be deprived
of it by some extraordinary and excessive force; and if he should be so
deprived of it, whenever anything sinister happens to the usurper, he will
regain it. We have in Italy, for example, the Duke of Ferrara, who could
not have withstood the attacks of the Venetians in '84, nor those of Pope
Julius in '10, unless he had been long established in his dominions. For
the hereditary prince has less cause and less necessity to offend; hence
it happens that he will be more loved; and unless extraordinary vices cause
him to be hated, it is reasonable to expect that his subjects will be naturally
well disposed towards him; and in the antiquity and duration of his rule
the memories and motives that make for change are lost, for one change
always leaves the toothing for another.
CHAPTER 3
CONCERNING MIXED PRINCIPALITIES
BUT the difficulties occur in a new
principality. And firstly, if it be not entirely new, but is, as it were,
a member of a state which, taken collectively, may be called composite,
the changes arise chiefly from an inherent difficulty which there is in
all new principalities; for men change their rulers willingly, hoping to
better themselves, and this hope induces them to take up arms against him
who rules: wherein they are deceived, because they afterwards find by experience
they have gone from bad to worse. This follows also on another natural
and common necessity, which always causes a new prince to burden those
who have submitted to him with his soldiery and with infinite other hardships
which he must put upon his new acquisition. In this way you have enemies
in all those whom you have injured in seizing that principality, and you
are not able to keep those friends who put you there because of your not
being able to satisfy them in the way they expected, and you cannot take
strong measures against them, feeling bound to them. For, although one
may be very strong in armed forces, yet in entering a province one has
always need of the goodwill of the natives. For these reasons Louis XII,
King of France, quickly occupied Milan, and as quickly lost it; and to
turn him out the first time it only needed Lodovico's own forces; because
those who had opened the gates to him, finding themselves deceived in their
hopes of future benefit, would not endure the ill-treatment of the new
prince. It is very true that, after acquiring rebellious provinces a second
time, they are not so lightly lost afterwards, because the prince, with
little reluctance, takes the opportunity of the rebellion to punish the
delinquents, to clear out the suspects, and to strengthen himself in the
weakest places. Thus to cause France to lose Milan the first time it was
enough for the Duke Lodovico to raise insurrections on the borders; but
to cause him to lose it a second time it was necessary to bring the whole
world against him, and that his armies should be defeated and driven out
of Italy; which followed from the causes above mentioned. Nevertheless
Milan was taken from France both the first and the second time. The general
reasons for the first have been discussed; it remains to name those for
the second, and to see what resources he had, and what any one in his situation
would have had for maintaining himself more securely in his acquisition
than did the King of France. Now I say that those dominions which, when
acquired, are added to an ancient state by him who acquires them, are either
of the same country and language, or they are not. When they are, it is
easier to hold them, especially when they have not been accustomed to self-government;
and to hold them securely it is enough to have destroyed the family of
the prince who was ruling them; because the two peoples, preserving in
other things the old conditions, and not being unlike in customs, will
live quietly together, as one has seen in Brittany, Burgundy, Gascony,
and Normandy, which have been bound to France for so long a time: and,
although there may be some difference in language, nevertheless the customs
are alike, and the people will easily be able to get on amongst themselves.
He who has annexed them, if he wishes to hold them, has only to bear in
mind two considerations: the one, that the family of their former lord
is extinguished; the other, that neither their laws nor their taxes are
altered, so that in a very short time they will become entirely one body
with the old principality. But when states are acquired in a country differing
in language, customs, or laws, there are difficulties, and good fortune
and great energy are needed to hold them, and one of the greatest and most
real helps would be that he who has acquired them should go and reside
there. This would make his position more secure and durable, as it has
made that of the Turk in Greece, who, notwithstanding all the other measures
taken by him for holding that state, if he had not settled there, would
not have been able to keep it. Because, if one is on the spot, disorders
are seen as they spring up, and one can quickly remedy them; but if one
is not at hand, they heard of only when they are one can no longer remedy
them. Besides this, the country is not pillaged by your officials; the
subjects are satisfied by prompt recourse to the prince; thus, wishing
to be good, they have more cause to love him, and wishing to be otherwise,
to fear him. He who would attack that state from the outside must have
the utmost caution; as long as the prince resides there it can only be
wrested from him with the greatest difficulty. The other and better course
is to send colonies to one or two places, which may be as keys to that
state, for it necessary either to do this or else to keep there a great
number of cavalry and infantry. A prince does not spend much on colonies,
for with little or no expense he can send them out and keep them there,
and he offends a minority only of the citizens from whom he takes lands
and houses to give them to the new inhabitants; and those whom he offends,
remaining poor and scattered, are never able to injure him; whilst the
rest being uninjured are easily kept quiet, and at the same time are anxious
not to err for fear it should happen to them as it has to those who have
been despoiled. In conclusion, I say that these colonies are not costly,
they are more faithful, they injure less, and the injured, as has been
said, I being poor and scattered, cannot hurt. Upon this, one has to remark
that men ought either to be well treated or crushed, because they can avenge
themselves of lighter injuries, of more serious ones they cannot; therefore
the injury that is to be done to a man ought to be of such a kind that
one does not stand in fear of revenge. But in maintaining armed men there
in place of colonies one spends much more, having to consume on the garrison
all income from the state, so that the acquisition turns into a loss, and
many more are exasperated, because the whole state is injured; through
the shifting of the garrison up and down all become acquainted with hardship,
and all become hostile, and they are enemies who, whilst beaten on their
own ground, are yet able to do hurt. For every reason, therefore, such
guards are as useless as a colony is useful. Again, the prince who holds
a country differing in the above respects ought to make himself the head
and defender of his powerful neighbours, and to weaken the more powerful
amongst them, taking care that no foreigner as powerful as himself shall,
by any accident, get a footing there; for it will always happen that such
a one will be introduced by those who are discontented, either through
excess of ambition or through fear, as one has seen already. The Romans
were brought into Greece by the Aetolians; and in every other country where
they obtained a footing they were brought in by the inhabitants. And the
usual course of affairs is that, as soon as a powerful foreigner enters
a country, all the subject states are drawn to him, moved by the hatred
which they feel against the ruling power. So that in respect to these subject
states he has not to take any trouble to gain them over to himself, for
the whole of them quickly rally to the state which he has acquired there.
He has only to take care that they do not get hold of too much power and
too much authority, and then with his own forces, and with their goodwill,
he can easily keep down the more powerful of them, so as to remain entirely
master in the country. And he who does not properly manage this business
will soon lose what he has acquired, and whilst he does hold it he will
have endless difficulties and troubles. The Romans, in the countries which
they annexed, observed closely these measures; they sent colonies and maintained
friendly relations with the minor powers, without increasing their strength;
they kept down the greater, and did not allow any strong foreign powers
to gain authority. Greece appears to me sufficient for an example. The
Achaeans and Aetolians were kept friendly by them, the kingdom of Macedonia
was humbled, Antiochus was driven out; yet the merits of the Achaeans and
Aetolians never secured for them permission to increase their power, nor
did the persuasions of Philip ever induce the Romans to be his friends
without first humbling him, nor did the influence of Antiochus make them
agree that he should retain any lordship over the country. Because the
Romans did in these instances what all prudent princes ought to do, who
have to regard not only present troubles, but also future ones, for which
they must prepare with every energy, because, when foreseen, it is easy
to remedy them; but if you wait until they approach, the medicine is no
longer in time because the malady has become incurable; for it happens
in this, as the physicians say it happens in hectic fever, that in the
beginning of the malady it is easy to cure but difficult to detect, but
in the course of time, not having been either detected or treated in the
beginning, it becomes easy to detect but difficult to cure. Thus it happens
in affairs of state, for when the evils that arise have been foreseen (which
it is only given to a wise man to see), they can be quickly redressed,
but when, through not having been foreseen, they have been permitted to
grow in a way that every one can see them. there is no longer a remedy.
Therefore, the Romans, foreseeing troubles, dealt with them at once, and,
even to avoid a war, would not let them come to a head, for they knew that
war is not to be avoided, but is only put off to the advantage of others;
moreover they wished to fight with Philip and Antiochus in Greece so as
not to have to do it in Italy; they could have avoided both, but this they
did not wish; nor did that ever please them which is for ever in the mouths
of the wise ones of our time:- Let us enjoy the benefits of the time- but
rather the benefits of their own valour and prudence, for time drives everything
before it, and is able to bring with it good as well as evil, and evil
as well as good. But let us turn to France and inquire whether she has
done any of the things mentioned. I will speak of Louis [XII] (and not
of Charles [VIII]) as the one whose conduct is the better to be observed,
he having held possession of Italy for the longest period; and you will
see that he has done the opposite to those things which ought to be done
to retain a state composed of divers elements. King Louis was brought into
Italy by the ambition of the Venetians, who desired to obtain half the
state of Lombardy by his intervention. I will not blame the course taken
by the king, because, wishing to get a foothold in Italy, and having no
friends there- seeing rather that every door was shut to him owing to the
conduct of Charles- he was forced to accept those friendships which he
could get, and he would have succeeded very quickly in his design if in
other matters he had not made some mistakes. The king, however, having
acquired Lombardy, regained at once the authority which Charles had lost:
Genoa yielded; the Florentines became his friends; the Marquess of Mantua,
the Duke of Ferrara, the Bentivoglio, my lady of Forli, the Lords of Faenza,
of Pesaro, of Rimini, of Camerino, of Piombino, the Lucchesi, the Pisans,
the Sienese- everybody made advances to him to become his friend. Then
could the Venetians realize the rashness of the course taken by them, which,
in order that they might secure two towns in Lombardy, had made the king
master of two-thirds of Italy. Let any one now consider with what little
difficulty the king could have maintained his position in Italy had he
observed the rules above laid down, and kept all his friends secure and
protected; for although they were numerous they were both weak and timid,
some afraid of the Church, some of the Venetians, and thus they would always
have been forced to stand in with him, and by their means he could easily
have made himself secure against those who remained powerful. But he was
no sooner in Milan than he did the contrary by assisting Pope Alexander
to occupy the Romagna. It never occurred to him that by this action he
was weakening himself, depriving himself of friends and those who had thrown
themselves into his lap, whilst he aggrandized the Church by adding much
temporal power to the spiritual, thus giving it great authority. And having
committed this prime error, he was obliged to follow it up, so much so
that, to put an end to the ambition of Alexander, and to prevent his becoming
the master of Tuscany, he was himself forced to come into Italy. And as
if it were not enough to have aggrandized the Church, and deprived himself
friends, he, wishing to have the kingdom of Naples, divides it with the
King of Spain, and where he was the prime arbiter of Italy he takes an
associate, so that the ambitious of that country and the malcontents of
his own should have where to shelter; and whereas he could have left in
the kingdom his own pensioner as king, he drove him out, to put one there
who was able to drive him, Louis, out in turn. The wish to acquire is in
truth very natural and common, and men always do so when they can, and
for this they will be praised not blamed; but when they cannot do so, yet
wish to do so by any means, then there is folly and blame. Therefore, if
France could have attacked Naples with her own forces she ought to have
done so; if she could not, then she ought not to have divided it. And if
the partition which she made with the Venetians in Lombardy was justified
by the excuse that by it she got a foothold in Italy, this other partition
merited blame, for it had not the excuse of that necessity. Therefore Louis
made these five errors: he destroyed the minor powers, he increased the
strength of one of the greater powers in Italy, he brought in a foreign
power, he did not settle in the country, he did not send colonies. Which
errors, if he had lived, were not enough to injure him had he not made
a sixth by taking away their dominions from the Venetians; because, had
he not aggrandized the Church, nor brought Spain into Italy, it would have
been very reasonable and necessary to humble them; but having first taken
these steps, he ought never to have consented to their ruin, for they,
being powerful, would always have kept off others from designs on Lombardy,
to which the Venetians would never have consented except to become masters
themselves there; also because the others would not wish to take Lombardy
from France in order to give it to the Venetians, and to run counter to
both they would not have had the courage. And if any one should say: King
Louis yielded the Romagna to Alexander and the kingdom to Spain to avoid
war, I answer for the reasons given above that a blunder ought never be
perpetrated to avoid war, because it is not to be avoided, but is only
deferred to your disadvantage. And if another should allege the pledge
which the king had given to the Pope that he would assist him in the enterprise,
in exchange for the dissolution of his marriage and for the hat to Rouen,
to that I reply what I shall write later on concerning the faith of princes,
and how it ought to be kept. Thus King Louis lost Lombardy by not having
followed any of the conditions observed by those who have taken possession
of countries and wished to retain them. Nor is there any miracle in this,
but much that is reasonable and quite natural. And on these matters I spoke
at Nantes with Rouen, when Valentino, as Cesare Borgia, the son of Pope
Alexander, was usually called, occupied the Romagna, and on Cardinal Rouen
observing to me that the Italians did not understand war, I replied to
him that the French did not understand statecraft, meaning that otherwise
they would not have allowed the Church to reach such greatness. And in
fact it has been seen that the greatness of the Church and of Spain in
Italy has been caused by France, and her ruin may be attributed to them.
From this a general rule is drawn which never or rarely fails: that he
who is the cause of another becoming powerful is ruined; because that predominancy
has been brought about either by astuteness or else by force, and both
are distrusted by him who has been raised to power. So called- in
Italian- from the duchy of Valentinois, conferred on him by Louis XII
CHAPTER 4
WHY THE KINGDOM OF DARIUS, CONQUERED
BY ALEXANDER, DID NOT REBEL AGAINST THE SUCCESSORS OF ALEXANDER AT HIS
DEATH
CONSIDERING the difficulties which men
have had to hold a newly acquired state, some might wonder how, seeing
that Alexander the Great became the master of Asia in a few years, and
died whilst it was yet scarcely settled (whence it might appear reasonable
that the whole empire would have rebelled), nevertheless his successors
maintained themselves, and had to meet no other difficulty than that which
arose among themselves from their own ambitions. I answer that the principalities
of which one has record are found to be governed in two different ways:
either by a prince, with a body of servants, who assist him to govern the
kingdom as ministers by his favour and permission; or by a prince and barons,
who hold that dignity by antiquity of blood and not by the grace of the
prince. Such barons have states and their own subjects, who recognize them
as lords and hold them in natural affection. Those states that are governed
by a prince and his servants hold their prince in more consideration, because
in all the country there is no one who is recognized as superior to him,
and if they yield obedience to another they do it as to a minister and
official, and they do not bear him any particular affection. The examples
of these two governments in our time are the Turk and the King of France.
The entire monarchy of the Turk is governed by one lord, the others are
his servants; and, dividing his kingdom into sanjaks, he sends there different
administrators, and shifts and changes them as he chooses. But the King
of France is placed in the midst of an ancient body of lords, acknowledged
by their own subjects, and beloved by them; they have their own prerogatives,
nor can the king take these away except at his peril. Therefore, he who
considers both of these states will recognize great difficulties in seizing
the state of the Turk, but, once it is conquered, great ease in holding
it. The causes of the difficulties in seizing the kingdom of the Turk are
that the usurper cannot be called in by the princes of the kingdom, nor
can he hope to be assisted in his designs by the revolt of those whom the
lord has around him. This arises from the reasons given above; for his
ministers, being all slaves and bondmen, can only be corrupted with great
difficulty, and one can expect little advantage from them when they have
been corrupted, as they cannot carry the people with them, for the reasons
assigned. Hence, he who attacks the Turk must bear in mind that he will
find him united, and he will have to rely more on his own strength than
on the revolt of others; but, if once the Turk has been conquered, and
routed in the field in such a way that he cannot replace his armies, there
is nothing to fear but the family of the prince, and, this being exterminated,
there remains no one to fear, the others having no credit with the people;
and as the conqueror did not rely on them before his victory, so he ought
not to fear them after it. The contrary happens in kingdoms governed like
that of France, because one can easily enter there by gaining over some
baron of the kingdom, for one always finds malcontents and such as desire
a change. Such men, for the reasons given, can open the way into the state
and render the victory easy; but if you wish to hold it afterwards, you
meet with infinite difficulties, both from those who have assisted you
and from those you have crushed. Nor is it enough for you to have exterminated
the family of the prince, because the lords that remain make themselves
the heads of fresh movements against you, and as you are unable either
to satisfy or exterminate them, that state is lost whenever time brings
the opportunity. Now if you will consider what was the nature of the government
of Darius, you will find it similar to the kingdom of the Turk, and therefore
it was only necessary for Alexander, first to overthrow him in the field,
and then to take the country from him. After which victory, Darius being
killed, the state remained secure to Alexander, for the above reasons.
And if his successors had been united they would have enjoyed it securely
and at their ease, for there were no tumults raised in the kingdom except
those they provoked themselves. But it is impossible to hold with such
tranquillity states constituted like that of France. Hence arose those
frequent rebellions against the Romans in Spain, France, and Greece, owing
to the many principalities there were in these states, of which, as long
as the memory of them endured, the Romans always held an insecure possession;
but with the power and long continuance of the empire the memory of them
passed away, and the Romans then became secure possessors. And when fighting
afterwards amongst themselves, each one was able to attach to himself his
own parts of the country, according to the authority he had assumed there;
and the family of the former lord being exterminated, none other than the
Romans were acknowledged. When these things are remembered no one will
marvel at the ease with which Alexander held the Empire of Asia, or at
the difficulties which others have had to keep an acquisition, such as
Pyrrhus and many more; this is not occasioned by the little or abundance
of ability in the conqueror, but by the want of uniformity in the subject
state.
CHAPTER 5
CONCERNING THE WAY TO GOVERN CITIES
OR PRINCIPALITIES WHICH LIVED UNDER THEIR OWN LAWS BEFORE THEY WERE ANNEXED
WHENEVER those states which have been
acquired as stated have been accustomed to live under their own laws and
in freedom, there are three courses for those who wish to hold them: the
first is to ruin them, the next is to reside there in person, the third
is to permit them to live under their own laws, drawing a tribute, and
establishing within it an oligarchy which will keep it friendly to you.
Because such a government, being created by the prince, knows that it cannot
stand without his friendship and interest, and does its utmost to support
him; and therefore he who would keep a city accustomed to freedom will
hold it more easily by the means of its own citizens than in any other
way. There are, for example, the Spartans and the Romans. The Spartans
held Athens and Thebes, establishing there an oligarchy, nevertheless they
lost them. The Romans, in order to hold Capua, Carthage, and Numantia,
dismantled them, and did not lose them. They wished to hold Greece as the
Spartans held it, making it free and permitting its laws, and did not succeed.
So to hold it they were compelled to dismantle many cities in the country,
for in truth there is no safe way to retain them otherwise than by ruining
them. And he who becomes master of a city accustomed to freedom and does
not destroy it, may expect to be destroyed by it, for in rebellion it has
always the watch-word of liberty and its ancient privileges as a rallying
point, which neither time nor benefits will ever cause it to forget. And
what ever you may do or provide against, they never forget that name or
their privileges unless they are disunited or dispersed but at every chance
they immediately rally to them, as Pisa after the hundred years she had
been held in bondage by the Florentines. But when cities or countries are
accustomed to live under a prince, and his family is exterminated, they,
being on the one hand accustomed to obey and on the other hand not having
the old prince, cannot agree in making one from amongst themselves, and
they do not know how to govern themselves. For this reason they are very
slow to take up arms, and a prince can gain them to himself and secure
them much more easily. But in republics there is more vitality, greater
hatred, and more desire for vengeance, which will never permit them to
allow the memory of their former liberty to rest; so that the safest way
is to destroy them or to reside there.
CHAPTER 6
CONCERNING NEW PRINCIPALITIES WHICH
ARE ACQUIRED BY ONE'S OWN ARMS AND ABILITY
LET no one be surprised if, in speaking
of entirely new principalities as I shall do, I adduce the highest examples
both of prince and of state; because men, walking almost always in paths
beaten by others, and following by imitation their deeds, are yet unable
to keep entirely to the ways of others or attain to the power of those
they imitate. A wise man ought always to follow the paths beaten by great
men, and to imitate those who have been supreme, so that if his ability
does not equal theirs, at least it will savour of it. Let him act like
the clever archers who, designing to hit the mark which yet appears too
far distant, and knowing the limits to which the strength of their bow
attains, take aim much higher than the mark, not to reach by their strength
or arrow to so great a height, but to be able with the aid of so high an
aim to hit the mark they wish to reach. I say, therefore, that in entirely
new principalities, where there is a new prince, more or less difficulty
is found in keeping them, accordingly as there is more or less ability
in him who has acquired the state. Now, as the fact of becoming a prince
from a private station presupposes either ability or fortune, it is clear
that one or other of these two things will mitigate in some degree many
difficulties. Nevertheless, he who has relied least on fortune is established
the strongest. Further, it facilitates matters when the prince, having
no other state, is compelled to reside there in person. But to come to
those who, by their own ability and not through fortune, have risen to
be princes, I say that Moses, Cyrus, Romulus, Theseus, and such like are
the most excellent examples. And although one may not discuss Moses, he
having been a mere executor of the will of God, yet he ought to be admired,
if only for that favour which made him worthy to speak with God. But in
considering Cyrus and others who have acquired or founded kingdoms, all
will be found admirable; and if their particular deeds and conduct shall
be considered, they will not be found inferior to those of Moses, although
he had so great a preceptor. And in examining their actions and lives one
cannot see that they owed anything to fortune beyond opportunity, which
brought them the material to mould into the form which seemed best to them.
Without that opportunity their powers of mind would have been extinguished,
and without those powers the opportunity would have come in vain. It was
necessary, therefore, to Moses that he should find the people of Israel
in Egypt enslaved and oppressed by the Egyptians, in order that they should
be disposed to follow him so as to be delivered out of bondage. It was
necessary that Romulus should not remain in Alba, and that he should be
abandoned at his birth, in order that he should become King of Rome and
founder of the fatherland. It was necessary that Cyrus should find the
Persians discontented with the government of the Medes, and the Medes soft
and effeminate through their long peace. Theseus could not have shown his
ability had he not found the Athenians dispersed. These opportunities,
therefore, made those men fortunate, and their high ability enabled them
to recognize the opportunity whereby their country was ennobled and made
famous. Those who by valorous ways become princes, like these men, acquire
a principality with difficulty, but they it with ease. The difficulties
they have in acquiring it arise in part from the new rules and methods
which they are forced to introduce to establish their government and its
security. And it ought to be remembered that there is nothing more difficult
to take in hand, more perilous to conduct, or more uncertain in its success,
than to take the lead in the introduction of a new order of things. Because
the innovator has for enemies all those who have done well under the old
conditions, and lukewarm defenders in those who may do well under the new.
This coolness arises partly from fear of the opponents, who have the laws
on their side, and partly from the incredulity of men, who do not readily
believe in new things until they have had a long experience of them. Thus
it happens that whenever those who are hostile have the opportunity to
attack they do it like partisans, whilst the others defend lukewarmly,
in such wise that the prince is endangered along with them. It is necessary,
therefore, if we desire to discuss this matter thoroughly, to inquire whether
these innovators can rely on themselves or have to depend on others: that
is to say, whether, to consummate their enterprise, have they to use prayers
or can they use force? In the first instance they always succeed badly,
and never compass anything; but when they can rely on themselves and use
force, then they are rarely endangered. Hence it is that all armed prophets
have conquered, and the unarmed ones have been destroyed. Besides the reasons
mentioned, the nature of the people is variable, and whilst it is easy
to persuade them, it is difficult to fix them in that persuasion. And thus
it is necessary to take such measures that, when they believe no longer,
it may be possible to make them believe by force. If Moses, Cyrus, Theseus,
and Romulus had been unarmed they could not have enforced their constitutions
for long- as happened in our time to Fra Girolamo Savonarola, who was ruined
with his new order of things immediately the multitude believed in him
no longer, and he had no means of keeping steadfast those who believed
or of making the unbelievers to believe. Therefore such as these have great
difficulties in consummating their enterprise, for all their dangers are
in the ascent, yet with ability they will overcome them; but when these
are overcome, and those who envied them their success are exterminated,
they will begin to be respected, and they will continue afterwards powerful,
secure, honoured, and happy. To these great examples I wish to add a lesser
one; still it bears some resemblance to them, and I wish it to suffice
me for all of a like kind: it is Hiero the Syracusan. This man rose from
a private station to be Prince of Syracuse, nor did he, either, owe anything
to fortune but opportunity; for the Syracusans, being oppressed, chose
him for their captain, afterwards he was rewarded by being made their prince.
He was of so great ability, even as a private citizen, that one who writes
of him says he wanted nothing but a kingdom to be a king. This man abolished
the old soldiery, organized the new, gave up old alliances, made new ones;
and as he had his own soldiers and allies, on such foundations he was able
to build any edifice: thus, whilst he had endured much trouble in acquiring,
he had but little in keeping.
CHAPTER 7
CONCERNING NEW PRINCIPALITIES WHICH
ARE ACQUIRED EITHER BY THE ARMS OF OTHERS OR BY GOOD FORTUNE
THOSE who solely by good fortune become
princes from being private citizens have little trouble in rising, but
much in keeping atop; they have not any difficulties on the way up, because
they fly, but they have many when they reach the summit. Such are those
to whom some state is given either for money or by the favour of him who
bestows it; as happened to many in Greece, in the cities of Ionia and of
the Hellespont, where princes were made by Darius, in order that they might
hold the cities both for his security and his glory; as also were those
emperors who, by the corruption of the soldiers, from being citizens came
to empire. Such stand simply upon the goodwill and the fortune of him who
has elevated them- two most inconstant and unstable things. Neither have
they the knowledge requisite for the position; because, unless they are
men of great worth and ability, it is not reasonable to expect that they
should know how to command, having always lived in a private condition;
besides, they cannot hold it because they have not forces which they can
keep friendly and faithful. States that rise unexpectedly, then, like all
other things in nature which are born and grow rapidly, cannot have their
foundations and relations with other states fixed in such a way that the
first storm will not overthrow them; unless, as is said, those who unexpectedly
become princes are men of so much ability that they know they have to be
prepared at once to hold that which fortune has thrown into their laps,
and that those foundations, which others have laid before they became princes,
they must lay afterwards. Concerning these two methods of rising to be
a prince by ability or fortune, I wish to adduce two examples within our
own recollection, and these are Francesco Sforza and Cesare Borgia. Francesco,
by proper means and with great ability, from being a private person rose
to be Duke of Milan, and that which he had acquired with a thousand anxieties
he kept with little trouble. On the other hand, Cesare Borgia, called by
the people Duke Valentino, acquired his state during the ascendancy of
his father, and on its decline he lost it, notwithstanding that he had
taken every measure and done all that ought to be done by a wise and able
man to fix firmly his roots in the states which the arms and fortunes of
others had bestowed on him. Because, as is stated above, he who has not
first laid his foundations may be able with great ability to lay them afterwards,
but they will be laid with trouble to the architect and danger to the building.
If, therefore, all the steps taken by the duke be considered, it will be
seen that he laid solid foundations for his future power, and I do not
consider it superfluous to discuss them, because I do not know what better
precepts to give a new prince than the example of his actions; and if his
dispositions were of no avail, that was not his fault, but the extraordinary
and extreme malignity of fortune. Alexander VI, in wishing to aggrandize
the duke, his son, had many immediate and prospective difficulties. Firstly,
he did not see his way to make him master of any state that was not a state
of the Church; and if he was willing to rob the Church he knew that the
Duke of Milan and the Venetians would not consent, because Faenza and Rimini
were already under the protection of the Venetians. Besides this, he saw
the arms of Italy, especially those by which he might have been assisted,
in hands that would fear the aggrandizement of the Pope, namely, the Orsini
and the Colonna and their following. It behoved him, therefore, to upset
this state of affairs and embroil the powers, so as to make himself securely
master of part of their states. This was easy for him to do, because he
found the Venetians, moved by other reasons, inclined to bring back the
French into Italy; he would not only not oppose this, but he would render
it more easy by dissolving the former marriage of King Louis. Therefore
the king came into Italy with the assistance of the Venetians and the consent
of Alexander. He was no sooner in Milan than the Pope had soldiers from
him for the attempt on the Romagna, which yielded to him on the reputation
of the king. The duke, therefore, having acquired the Romagna and beaten
the Colonna, while wishing to hold that and to advance further, was hindered
by two things: the one, his forces did not appear loyal to him, the other,
the goodwill of France: that is to say, he feared that the forces of the
Orsini, which was using, would not stand to him, that not only might they
hinder him from winning more, but might themselves seize what he had won,
and that the King might also do the same. Of the Orsini he had a warning
when, after taking Faenza and attacking Bologna, he saw them go very unwillingly
to that attack. And as to the king, he learned his mind when he himself,
after taking the duchy of Urbino, attacked Tuscany, and the king made him
desist from that undertaking; hence the duke decided to depend no more
upon the arms and the luck of others. For the first thing he weakened the
Orsini and Colonna parties in Rome, by gaining to himself all their adherents
who were gentlemen, making them his gentlemen, giving them good pay, and,
according to their rank, honouring them with office and command in such
a way that in a few months all attachment to the factions was destroyed
and turned entirely to the duke. After this he awaited an opportunity to
crush the Orsini, having scattered the adherents of the Colonna. This came
to him soon and he used it well; for the Orsini, perceiving at length that
the aggrandizement of the duke and the Church was ruin to them, called
a meeting at Magione, in the territory of Perugia. From this sprung the
rebellion at Urbino and the tumults in the Romagna, with endless dangers
to the duke, all of which he overcame with the help of the French. Having
restored his authority, not to leave it at risk by trusting either to the
French or other outside forces, he had recourse to his wiles, and he knew
so well how to conceal his mind that, by the mediation of Signor Paolo
[Orsini]- whom the duke did not fail to secure with all kinds of attention,
giving him money, apparel, and horses- the Orsini were reconciled, so that
their simplicity brought them into his power at Sinigaglia. Having exterminated
the leaders, and turned their partisans into his friends, the duke had
laid sufficiently good foundations to his power, having all the Romagna
and the duchy of Urbino; and the people now beginning to appreciate their
prosperity, he gained them all over to himself. And as this point is worthy
of notice, and to be imitated by others, I am not willing to leave it out.
When the duke occupied the Romagna he found it under the rule of weak masters,
who rather plundered their subjects than ruled them, and gave them more
cause for disunion than for union, so that the country was full of robbery,
quarrels, and every kind of violence; and so, wishing to bring back peace
and obedience to authority, he considered it necessary to give it a good
governor. Thereupon he promoted Messer Ramiro d'Orco [de Lorqua], a swift
and cruel man, to whom he gave the fullest power. This man in a short time
restored peace and unity with the greatest success. Afterwards the duke
considered that it was not advisable to confer such excessive authority,
for he had no doubt but that he would become odious, so he set up a court
of judgment in the country, under a most excellent president, wherein all
cities had their advocates. And because he knew that the past severity
had caused some hatred against himself, so, to clear himself in the minds
of the people, and gain them entirely to himself, he desired to show that,
if any cruelty had been practised, it had not originated with him, but
in the natural sternness of the minister. Under this pretence he took Ramiro,
and one morning caused him to be executed and left on the piazza at Cesena
with the block and a bloody knife at his side. The barbarity of this spectacle
caused the people to be at once satisfied and dismayed. But let us return
whence we started. I say that the duke, finding himself now sufficiently
powerful and partly secured from immediate dangers by having armed himself
in his own way, and having in a great measure crushed those forces in his
vicinity that could injure him if he wished to proceed with his conquest,
had next to consider France, for he knew that the king, who too late was
aware of his mistake, would not support him. And from this time he began
to seek new alliances and to temporize with France in the expedition which
she was making towards the kingdom of Naples against the Spaniards who
were besieging Gaeta. It was his intention to secure himself against them,
and this he would have quickly accomplished had Alexander lived. Such was
his line of action as to present affairs. But as to the future he had to
fear, in the first place, that a new successor to the Church might not
be friendly to him and might seek to take from him that which Alexander
had given him, so he decided to act in four ways. Firstly, by exterminating
the families of those lords whom he had despoiled, so as to take away that
pretext from the Pope. Secondly, by winning to himself all the gentlemen
of Rome, so as to be able to curb the Pope with their aid, as has been
observed. Thirdly, by converting the college more to himself. Fourthly,
by acquiring so much power before the Pope should die that he could by
his own measures resist the first shock. Of these four things, at the death
of Alexander, he had accomplished three. For he had killed as many of the
dispossessed lords as he could lay hands on, and few had escaped; he had
won over the Roman gentlemen, and he had the most numerous party in the
college. And as to any fresh acquisition, he intended to become master
of Tuscany, for he already possessed Perugia and Piombino, and Pisa was
under his protection. And as he had no longer to study France (for the
French were already driven out of the kingdom of Naples by the Spaniards,
and in this way both were compelled to buy his goodwill), he pounced down
upon Pisa. After this, Lucca and Siena yielded at once, partly through
hatred and partly through fear of the Florentines; and the Florentines
would have had no remedy had he continued to prosper, as he was prospering
the year that Alexander died, for he had acquired so much power and reputation
that he would have stood by himself, and no longer have depended on the
luck and the forces of others, but solely on his own power and ability.
But Alexander died five years after he had first drawn the sword. He left
the duke with the state of Romagna alone consolidated, with the rest in
the air, between two most powerful hostile armies, and sick unto death.
Yet there were in the duke such boldness and ability, and he knew so well
how men are to be won or lost, and so firm were the foundations which in
so short a time he had laid, that if he had not had those armies on his
back, or if he had been in good health, he would have overcome all difficulties.
And it is seen that his foundations were good, for the Romagna awaited
him for more than a month. In Rome, although but half alive, he remained
secure; and whilst the Baglioni, the Vitelli, and the Orsini might come
to Rome, they could not effect anything against him. If he could not have
made Pope him whom he wished, at least the one whom he did not wish would
not have been elected. But if he had been in sound health at the death
of Alexander, everything would have been easy to him. On the day that Julius
II was elected, he told me that he had thought of everything that might
occur at the death of his father, and had provided a remedy for all, except
that he had never anticipated that, when the death did happen, he himself
would be on the point to die. When all the actions of the duke are recalled,
I do not know how to blame him, but rather it appears to me, as I have
said, that I ought to offer him for imitation to all those who, by the
fortune or the arms of others, are raised to government. Because he, having
a lofty spirit and far-reaching aims, could not have regulated his conduct
otherwise, and only the shortness of the life of Alexander and his own
sickness frustrated his designs. Therefore, he who considers it necessary
to secure himself in his new principality, to win friends, to overcome
either by force or fraud, to make himself beloved and feared by the people,
to be followed and revered by the soldiers, to exterminate those who have
power or reason to hurt him, to change the old order of things for new,
to be severe and gracious, magnanimous and liberal, to destroy a disloyal
soldiery and to create new, to maintain friendship with kings and princes
in such a way that they must help him with zeal and offend with caution,
cannot find a more lively example than the actions of this man. Only can
he be blamed for the election of Julius II, in whom he made a bad choice,
because, as is said, not being able to elect a Pope to his own mind, he
could have hindered any other from being elected Pope; and he ought never
to have consented to the election of any cardinal whom he had injured or
who had cause to fear him if they became pontiffs. For men injure either
from fear or hatred. Those whom he had injured, amongst others, were San
Pietro ad Vincula, Colonna, San Giorgio, and Ascanio. Any one of the others,
on becoming Pope, would have had to fear him, Rouen and the Spaniards excepted;
the latter from their relationship and obligations, the former from his
influence, the kingdom of France having relations with him. Therefore,
above everything, the duke ought to have created a Spaniard Pope, and,
failing him, he ought to have consented to Rouen and not San Pietro ad
Vincula. He who believes that new benefits will cause great personages
to forget old injuries is deceived. Therefore, the duke erred in his choice,
and it was the cause of his ultimate ruin. Julius II had been Cardinal
of San Pietro ad Vincula; San Giorgio was Raffaells Riaxis, and Ascanio
was Cardinal Ascanio Sforza.
CHAPTER 8
CONCERNING THOSE WHO HAVE OBTAINED A
PRINCIPALITY BY WICKEDNESS
ALTHOUGH a prince may rise from a private
station in two ways, neither of which can be entirely attributed to fortune
or genius, yet it is manifest to me that I must not be silent on them,
although one could be more copiously treated when I discuss republics.
These methods are when, either by some wicked or nefarious ways, one ascends
to the principality, or when by the favour of his fellow-citizens a private
person becomes the prince of his country. And speaking of the first method,
it will be illustrated by two examples- one ancient, the other modern-
and without entering further into the subject, I consider these two examples
will suffice those who may be compelled to follow them. Agathocles, the
Sicilian, became King of Syracuse not only from a private but from a low
and abject position. This man, the son of a potter, through all the changes
in his fortunes always led an infamous life. Nevertheless, he accompanied
his infamies with so much ability of mind and body that, having devoted
himself to the military profession, he rose through its ranks to be Praetor
of Syracuse. Being established in that position, and having deliberately
resolved to make himself prince and to seize by violence, without obligation
to others, that which had been conceded to him by assent, he came to an
understanding for this purpose with Hamilcar, the Carthaginian, who, with
his army, was fighting in Sicily. One morning he assembled the people and
senate of Syracuse, as if he had to discuss with them things relating to
the Republic, and at a given signal the soldiers killed all the senators
and the richest of the people; these dead, he seized and held the princedom
of that city without any civil commotion. And although he was twice routed
by the Carthaginians, and ultimately besieged, yet not only was he able
to defend his city, but leaving part of his men for its defence, with the
others he attacked Africa, and in a short time raised the siege of Syracuse.
The Carthaginians, reduced to extreme necessity, were compelled to come
to terms with Agathocles, and, leaving Sicily to him, had to be content
with the possession of Africa. Therefore, he who considers the actions
and the genius of this man will see nothing, or little, which can be attributed
to fortune, inasmuch as he attained pre-eminence, as is shown above, not
by the favour of any one, but step by step in the military profession,
which steps were gained with a thousand troubles and perils, and were afterwards
boldly held by him with many hazards and dangers. Yet it cannot be called
talent to slay fellow-citizens, to deceive friends, to be without faith,
without mercy, without religion; such methods may gain empire, but not
glory. Still, if the courage of Agathocles in entering into and extricating
himself from dangers be considered, together with his greatness of mind
in enduring overcoming hardships, it cannot be seen why he should be esteemed
less than the most notable captain. Nevertheless, his barbarous cruelty
and inhumanity with infinite wickednesses do not permit him to be celebrated
among the most excellent men. What he achieved cannot be attributed either
to fortune or to genius. In our times, during the rule of Alexander VI,
Oliverotto da Fermo, having been left an orphan many years before, was
brought up by his maternal uncle, Giovanni Fogliani, and in the early days
of his youth sent to fight under Paolo Vitelli, that, being trained under
his discipline, he might attain some high position in the military profession.
After Paolo died, he fought under his brother Vitellozzo, and in a very
short time, being endowed with wit and a vigorous body and mind, he became
the first man in his profession. But it appearing to him a paltry thing
to serve under others, he resolved, with the aid of some citizens of Fermo,
to whom the slavery of their country was dearer than its liberty, and with
the help of the Vitelli, to seize Fermo. So he wrote to Giovanni Fogliani
that, having been away from home for many years, he wished to visit him
and his city, and in some measure to look into his patrimony; and although
he had not laboured to acquire anything except honour, yet, in order that
the citizens should see he had not spent his time in vain, he desired to
come honourably, so would be accompanied by one hundred horsemen, his friends
and retainers; and he entreated Giovanni to arrange that he should be received
honourably by the citizens of Fermo, all of which would be not only to
his honour, but also to that of Giovanni himself, who had brought him up.
Giovanni, therefore, did not fail in any attentions due to his nephew,
and he caused him to be honourably received by the Fermans, and he lodged
him in his own house, where, having passed some days, and having arranged
what was necessary for his wicked designs, Oliverotto gave a solemn banquet
to which he invited Giovanni Fogliani and the chiefs of Fermo. When the
viands and all the other entertainments that are usual in such banquets
were finished, Oliverotto artfully began certain grave discourses, speaking
of the greatness of Pope Alexander and his son Cesare, and of their enterprises,
to which discourse Giovanni and others answered; but he rose at once, saying
that such matters ought to be discussed in a more private place, and he
betook himself to a chamber, whither Giovanni and the rest of the citizens
went in after him. No sooner were they seated than soldiers issued from
secret places and slaughtered Giovanni and the rest. After these murders
Oliverotto, mounted on horseback, rode up and down the town and besieged
the chief magistrate in the palace, so that in fear the people were forced
to obey him, and to form a government, of which he made himself the prince.
He killed all the malcontents who were able to injure him, and strengthened
himself with new civil and military ordinances, in such a way that, in
the year during which he held the principality, not only was he secure
in the city of Fermo, but he had become formidable to all his neighbours.
And his destruction would have been as difficult as that of Agathocles
if he had not allowed himself to be overreached by Cesare Borgia, who took
him with the Orsini and Vitelli at Sinigaglia, as was stated above. Thus
one year after he had committed this parricide, he was strangled, together
with Vitellozzo, whom he had made his leader in valour and wickedness.
Some may wonder how it can happen that Agathocles, and his like, after
infinite treacheries and cruelties, should live for long secure in his
country, and defend himself from external enemies, and never be conspired
against by his own citizens; seeing that many others, by means of cruelty,
have never been able even in peaceful times to hold the state, still less
in the doubtful times of war. I believe that this follows from severities
being badly or properly used. Those may be called properly used, if of
evil it is lawful to speak well, that are applied at one blow and are necessary
to one's security, and that are not persisted in afterwards unless they
can be turned to the advantage of the subjects. The badly employed are
those which, notwithstanding they may be few in the commencement, multiply
with time rather than decrease. Those who practise the first system are
able, by aid of God or man, to mitigate in some degree their rule, as Agathocles
did. It is impossible for those who follow the other to maintain themselves.
Hence it is to be remarked that, in seizing a state, the usurper ought
to examine closely into all those injuries which it is necessary for him
to inflict, and to do them all at one stroke so as not to have to repeat
them daily; and thus by not unsettling men he will be able to reassure
them, and win them to himself by benefits. He who does otherwise, either
from timidity or evil advice, is always compelled to keep the knife in
his hand; neither can he rely on his subjects, nor can they attach themselves
to him, owing to their continued and repeated wrongs. For injuries ought
to be done all at one time, so that, being tasted less, they offend less;
benefits ought to be given little by little, so that the flavour of them
may last longer. And above all things, a prince ought to live amongst his
people in such a way that no unexpected circumstances, whether of good
or evil, shall make him change; because if the necessity for this comes
in troubled times, you are too late for harsh measures; and mild ones will
not help you, for they will be considered as forced from you, and no one
will be under any obligation to you for them.
CHAPTER 9
CONCERNING A CIVIL PRINCIPALITY
BUT coming to the other point- where
a leading citizen becomes the prince of his country, not by wickedness
or any intolerable violence, but by the favour of his fellow citizens-
this may be called a civil principality: nor is genius or fortune altogether
necessary to attain to it, but rather a happy shrewdness. I say then that
such a principality is obtained either by the favour of the people or by
the favour of the nobles. Because in all cities these two distinct parties
are found, and from this it arises that the people do not wish to be ruled
nor oppressed by the nobles, and the nobles wish to rule and oppress the
people; and from these two opposite desires there arises in cities one
of three results, either a principality, self-government, or anarchy. A
principality is created either by the people or by the nobles, accordingly
as one or other of them has the opportunity; for the nobles, seeing they
cannot withstand the people, begin to cry up the reputation of one of themselves,
and they make him a prince, so that under his shadow they can give vent
to their ambitions. The people, finding they cannot resist the nobles,
also cry up the reputation of one of themselves, and make him a prince
so as to be defended by his authority. He who obtains sovereignty by the
assistance of the nobles maintains himself with more difficulty than he
who comes to it by the aid of the people, because the former finds himself
with many around him who consider themselves his equals, and because of
this he can neither rule nor manage them to his liking. But he who reaches
sovereignty by popular favour finds himself alone, and has none around
him, or few, who are not prepared to obey him. Besides this, one cannot
by fair dealing, and without injury to others, satisfy the nobles, but
you can satisfy the people, for their object is more righteous than that
of the nobles, the latter wishing to oppress, whilst the former only desire
not to be oppressed. It is to be added also that a prince can never secure
himself against a hostile people, because of their being too many, whilst
from the nobles he can secure himself, as they are few in number. The worst
that a prince may expect from a hostile people is to be abandoned by them;
but from hostile nobles he has not only to fear abandonment, but also that
they will rise against him; for they, being in these affairs more far-seeing
and astute, always come forward in time to save themselves, and to obtain
favours from him whom they expect to prevail. Further, the prince is compelled
to live always with the same people, but he can do well without the same
nobles, being able to make and unmake them daily, and to give or take away
authority when it pleases him. Therefore, to make this point clearer, I
say that the nobles ought to be looked at mainly in two ways: that is to
say, they either shape their course in such a way as binds them entirely
to your fortune, or they do not. Those who so bind themselves, and are
not rapacious, ought to be honoured and loved; those who do not bind themselves
may be dealt with in two ways; they may fail to do this through pusillanimity
and a natural want of courage, in which case you ought to make use of them,
especially of those who are of good counsel; and thus, whilst in prosperity
you honour yourself, in adversity you have not to fear them. But when for
their own ambitious ends they shun binding themselves, it is a token that
they are giving more thought to themselves than to you, and a prince ought
to guard against such, and to fear them as if they were open enemies, because
in adversity they always help to ruin him. Therefore, one who becomes a
prince through the favour of the people ought to keep them friendly, and
this he can easily do seeing they only ask not to be oppressed by him.
But one who, in opposition to the people, becomes a prince by the favour
of the nobles, ought, above everything, to seek to win the people over
to himself, and this he may easily do if he takes them under his protection.
Because men, when they receive good from him of whom they were expecting
evil, are bound more closely to their benefactor; thus the people quickly
become more devoted to him than if he had been raised to the principality
by their favours; and the prince can win their affections in many ways,
but as these vary according to the circumstances one cannot give fixed
rules, so I omit them; but, I repeat, it is necessary for a prince to have
the people friendly, otherwise he has no security in adversity. Nabis,
Prince of the Spartans, sustained the attack of all Greece, and of a victorious
Roman army, and against them he defended his country and his government;
and for the overcoming of this peril it was only necessary for him to make
himself secure against a few, but this would not have been sufficient if
the people had been hostile. And do not let any one impugn this statement
with the trite proverb that 'He who builds on the people, builds on the
mud,' for this is true when a private citizen makes a foundation there,
and persuades himself that the people will free him when he is oppressed
by his enemies or by the magistrates; wherein he would find himself very
often deceived, as happened to the Gracchi in Rome and to Messer Giorgio
Scali in Florence. But granted a prince who has established himself as
above, who can command, and is a man of courage, undismayed in adversity,
who does not fail in other qualifications, and who, by his resolution and
energy, keeps the whole people encouraged- such a one will never find himself
deceived in them, and it will be shown that he has laid his foundations
well. These principalities are liable to danger when they are passing from
the civil to the absolute order of government, for such princes either
rule personally or through magistrates. In the latter case their government
is weaker and more insecure, because it rests entirely on the goodwill
of those citizens who are raised to the magistracy, and who, especially
in troubled times, can destroy the government with great ease, either by
intrigue or open defiance; and the prince has not the chance amid tumults
to exercise absolute authority, because the citizens and subjects, accustomed
to receive orders from magistrates, are not of a mind to obey him amid
these confusions, and there will always be in doubtful times a scarcity
of men whom he can trust. For such a prince cannot rely upon what he observes
in quiet times, when citizens had need of the state, because then every
one agrees with him; they all promise, and when death is far distant they
all wish to die for him; but in troubled times, when the state has need
of its citizens, then he finds but few. And so much the more is this experiment
dangerous, inasmuch as it can only be tried once. Therefore a wise prince
ought to adopt such a course that his citizens will always in every sort
and kind of circumstance have need of the state and of him, and then he
will always find them faithful.
CHAPTER 10
CONCERNING THE WAY IN WHICH THE STRENGTH
OF ALL PRINCIPALITIES OUGHT TO BE MEASURED
IT IS necessary to consider another
point in examining the character of these principalities: that is, whether
a prince has such power that, in case of need, he can support himself with
his own resources, or whether he has always need of the assistance of others.
And to make this quite clear I say that I consider those are able to support
themselves by their own resources who can, either by abundance of men or
money, raise a sufficient army to join battle against any one who comes
to attack them; and I consider those always to have need of others who
cannot show themselves against the enemy in the field, but are forced to
defend themselves by sheltering behind walls. The first case has been discussed,
but we will speak of it again should it recur. In the second case one can
say nothing except to encourage such princes to provision and fortify their
towns, and not on any account to defend the country. And whoever shall
fortify his town well, and shall have managed the other concerns of his
subjects in the way stated above, and to be often repeated, will never
be attacked without great caution, for men are always adverse to enterprises
where difficulties can be seen, and it will be seen not to be an easy thing
to attack one who has his town well fortified, and is not hated by his
people. The cities of Germany are absolutely free, they own but little
country around them, and they yield obedience to the emperor when it suits
them, nor do they fear this or any other power they may have near them,
because they are fortified in such a way that every one thinks the taking
of them by assault would be tedious and difficult, seeing they have proper
ditches and walls, they have sufficient artillery, and they always keep
in public depots enough for one year's eating, drinking, and firing. And
beyond this, to keep the people quiet and without loss to the state, they
always have the means of giving work to the community in those labours
that are the life and strength of the city, and on the pursuit of which
the people are supported; they also hold military exercises in repute,
and moreover have many ordinances to uphold them. Therefore, a prince who
has a strong city, and had not made himself odious, will not be attacked,
or if any one should attack he will only be driven off with disgrace; again,
because that affairs of this world are so changeable, it is almost impossible
to keep an army a whole year in the field without being interfered with.
And whoever should reply: If the people have property outside the city,
and see it burnt, they will not remain patient, and the long siege and
self-interest will make them forget their prince; to this I answer that
a powerful and courageous prince will overcome all such difficulties by
giving at one time hope to his subjects that the evil will not be for long,
at another time fear of the cruelty of the enemy, then preserving himself
adroitly from those subjects who seem to him to be too bold. Further, the
enemy would naturally on his arrival at once burn and ruin the country
at the time when the spirits of the people are still hot and ready for
the defence; and, therefore, so much the less ought the prince to hesitate;
because after a time, when spirits have cooled, the damage is already done,
the ills are incurred, and there is no longer any remedy; and therefore
they are so much the more ready to unite with their prince, he appearing
to be under obligations to them now that their houses have been burnt and
their possessions ruined in his defence. For it is the nature of men to
be bound by the benefits they confer as much as by those they receive.
Therefore, if everything is well considered, it wilt not be difficult for
a wise prince to keep the minds of his citizens steadfast from first to
last, when he does not fail to support and defend them.
CHAPTER 11
CONCERNING ECCLESIASTICAL PRINCIPALITIES
IT ONLY remains now to speak of ecclesiastical
principalities, touching which all difficulties are prior to getting possession,
because they are acquired either by capacity or good fortune, and they
can be held without either; for they are sustained by the ordinances of
religion, which are so all-powerful, and of such a character that the principalities
may be held no matter how their princes behave and live. These princes
alone have states and do not defend them, they have subjects and do not
rule them; and the states, although unguarded, are not taken from them,
and the subjects, although not ruled, do not care, and they have neither
the desire nor the ability to alienate themselves. Such principalities
only are secure and happy. But being upheld by powers, to which the human
mind cannot reach, I shall speak no more of them, because, being exalted
and maintained by God, it would be the act of a presumptuous and rash man
to discuss them. Nevertheless, if any one should ask of me how comes it
that the Church has attained such greatness in temporal power, seeing that
from Alexander backwards the Italian potentates (not only those who have
been called potentates, but every baron and lord, though the smallest)
have valued the temporal power very slightly- yet now a king of France
trembles before it, and it has been able to drive him from Italy, and to
ruin the Venetians- although this may be very manifest, it does not appear
to me superfluous to recall it in some measure to memory. Before Charles,
King of France, passed into Italy, this country was under the dominion
of the Pope, the Venetians, the King of Naples, the Duke of Milan, and
the Florentines. These potentates had two principal anxieties: the one,
that no foreigner should enter Italy under arms; the other, that none of
themselves should seize more territory. Those about whom there was the
most anxiety were the Pope and the Venetians. To restrain the Venetians
the union of all the others was necessary, as it was for the defence of
Ferrara; and to keep down the Pope they made use of the barons of Rome,
who, being divided into two factions, Orsini and Colonna, had always a
pretext for disorder, and, standing with arms in their hands under the
eyes of the Pontiff, kept the pontificate weak and powerless. And although
there might arise sometimes a courageous pope, such as Sixtus [IV], yet
neither fortune nor wisdom could rid him of these annoyances. And the short
life of a pope is also a cause of weakness; for in the ten years, which
is the average life of a pope, he can with difficulty lower one of the
factions; and if, so to speak, one pope should almost destroy the Colonna,
another would arise hostile to the Orsini, who would support their opponents,
and yet would not have time to ruin the Orsini. This was the reason why
the temporal powers of the pope were little esteemed in Italy. Alexander
VI arose afterwards, who of all the pontiffs that have ever been showed
how a pope with both money and arms was able to prevail; and through the
instrumentality of the Duke Valentino, and by reason of the entry of the
French, he brought about all those things which I have discussed above
in the actions of the duke. And although his intention was not to aggrandize
the Church, but the duke, nevertheless, what he did contributed to the
greatness of the Church, which, after his death and the ruin of the duke,
became the heir to all his labours. Pope Julius came afterwards and found
the Church strong, possessing all the Romagna, the barons of Rome reduced
to impotence, and, through the chastisements Alexander, the factions wiped
out; he also found the way open to accumulate money in a manner such as
had never been practised before Alexander's time. Such things Julius not
only followed, but improved upon, and he intended to gain Bologna, to ruin
the Venetians, and to drive the French out of Italy. All of these enterprises
prospered with him, and so much the more to his credit, inasmuch as he
did everything to strengthen the Church and not any private person. He
kept also the Orsini and Colonna factions within the bounds in which he
found them; and although there was among them some mind to make disturbance,
nevertheless he held two things firm: the one, the greatness of the church,
with which he terrified them; and the other, not allowing them to have
their own cardinals, who caused the disorders among them. For whenever
these factions have their cardinals they do not remain quiet for long,
because cardinals foster the factions in Rome and out of it, and the barons
are compelled to support them, and thus from the ambitions of prelates
arise disorders and tumults among the barons. For these reasons his Holiness
Pope Leo found the pontificate most powerful, and it is to be hoped that,
if others made it great in arms, he will make it still greater and more
venerated by his goodness and infinite other virtues.
CHAPTER 12
HOW MANY KINDS OF SOLDIERY THERE ARE,
AND CONCERNING MERCENARIES
HAVING discoursed particularly on the
characteristics of such principalities as in the beginning I proposed to
discuss, and having considered in some degree the causes of their being
good or bad, and having shown the methods by which many have sought to
acquire them and to hold them, it now remains for me to discuss generally
the means of offence and defence which belong to each of them. We have
seen above how necessary it is for a prince to have his foundations well
laid, otherwise it follows of necessity he will go to ruin. The chief foundations
of all states, new as well as old or composite, are good laws and good
arms; and as there cannot be good laws where the state is not well armed,
it follows that where they are well armed they have good laws. I shall
leave the laws out of the discussion and shall speak of the arms. I say,
therefore, that the arms with which a prince defends his state are either
his own, or they are mercenaries, auxiliaries, or mixed. Mercenaries and
auxiliaries are useless and dangerous; and if one holds his state based
on these arms, he will stand neither firm nor safe; for they are disunited,
ambitious and without discipline, unfaithful, valiant before friends, cowardly
before enemies; they have neither the fear of God nor fidelity to men,
and destruction is deferred only so long as the attack is; for in peace
one is robbed by them, and in war by the enemy. The fact is, they have
no other attraction or reason for keeping the field than a trifle of stipend,
which is not sufficient to make them willing to die for you. They are ready
enough to be your soldiers whilst you do not make war, but if war comes
they take themselves off or run from the foe; which I should have little
trouble to prove, for the ruin of Italy has been caused by nothing else
than by resting all her hopes for many years on mercenaries, and although
they formerly made some display and appeared valiant amongst themselves,
yet when the foreigners came they showed what they were. Thus it was that
Charles, King of France, was allowed to seize Italy with chalk in hand;
and he who told us that our sins were the cause of it told the truth, but
they were not the sins he imagined, but those which I have related. And
as they were the sins of princes, it is the princes who have also suffered
the penalty. With which to chalk up the billets for his soldiers.
I wish to demonstrate further the infelicity of these arms. The mercenary
captains are either capable men or they are not; if they are, you cannot
trust them, because they always aspire to their own greatness, either by
oppressing you, who are their master, or others contrary to your intentions;
but if the captain is not skilful, you are ruined in the usual way. And
if it be urged that whoever is armed will act in the same way, whether
mercenary or not, I reply that when arms have to be resorted to, either
by a prince or a republic, then the prince ought to go in person and perform
the duty of captain; the republic has to send its citizens, and when one
is sent who does not turn out satisfactorily, it ought to recall him, and
when one is worthy, to hold him by the laws so that he does not leave the
command. And experience has shown princes and republics, single-handed,
making the greatest progress, and mercenaries doing nothing except damage;
and it is more difficult to bring a republic, armed with its own arms,
under the sway of one of its citizens than it is to bring one armed with
foreign arms. Rome and Sparta stood for many ages armed and free. The Switzers
are completely armed and quite free. Of ancient mercenaries, for example,
there are the Carthaginians, who were oppressed by their mercenary soldiers
after the first war with the Romans, although the Carthaginians had their
own citizens for captains. After the death of Epaminondas, Philip of Macedon
was made captain of their soldiers by the Thebans, and after victory he
took away their liberty. Duke Filippo being dead, the Milanese enlisted
Francesco Sforza against the Venetians, and he, having overcome the enemy
at Caravaggio, allied himself with them to crush the Milanese, his masters.
His father, Sforza, having been engaged by Queen Johanna of Naples, left
her unprotected, so that she was forced to throw herself into the arms
of the King of Aragon, in order to save her kingdom. And if the Venetians
and Florentines formerly extended their dominions by these arms, and yet
their captains did not make themselves princes, but have defended them,
I reply that the Florentines in this case have been favoured by chance,
for of the able captains, of whom they might have stood in fear, some have
not conquered, some have been opposed, and others have turned their ambitions
elsewhere. One who did not conquer was Giovanni Acuto, and since he did
not conquer his fidelity cannot be proved; but every one will acknowledge
that, had he conquered, the Florentines would have stood at his discretion.
Sforza had the Bracceschi always against him, so they watched each other.
Francesco turned his ambition to Lombardy; Braccio against the Church and
the kingdom of Naples. But let us come to that which happened a short while
ago. The Florentines appointed as their captain Paolo Vitelli, a most prudent
man, who from a private position had risen to the greatest renown. If this
man had taken Pisa, nobody can deny that it would have been proper for
the Florentines to keep in with him, for if he became the soldier of their
enemies they had no means of resisting, and if they held to him they must
obey him. The Venetians, if their achievements are considered, will be
seen to have acted safely and gloriously so long as they sent to war their
own men, when with armed gentlemen and plebeians they did valiantly. This
was before they turned to enterprises on land, but when they began to fight
on land they forsook this virtue and followed the custom of Italy. And
in the beginning of their expansion on land, through not having much territory,
and because of their great reputation, they had not much to fear from their
captains; but when they expanded, as under Carmignola, they had a taste
of this mistake; for, having found him a most valiant man (they beat the
Duke of Milan under his leadership), and, on the other hand, knowing how
lukewarm he was in the war, they feared they would no longer conquer under
him, and for this reason they were not willing, nor were they able, to
let him go; and so, not to lose again that which they had acquired, they
were compelled, in order to secure themselves, to murder him. They had
afterwards for their captains Bartolomeo da Bergamo, Roberto da San Severino,
the Count of Pitigliano, and the like, under whom they had to dread loss
and not gain, as happened afterwards at Vaila, where in one battle they
lost that which in eight hundred years they had acquired with so much trouble.
Because from such arms conquests come but slowly, long delayed and inconsiderable,
but the losses sudden and portentous. As Sir John Hawkwood, the English
leader of mercenaries, was called by the Italians. And as with these examples
I have reached Italy, which has been ruled for many years by mercenaries,
I wish to discuss them more seriously, in order that, having seen their
rise and progress, one may be better prepared to counteract them. You must
understand that the empire has recently come to be repudiated in Italy,
that the Pope has acquired more temporal power, and that Italy has been
divided up into more states, for the reason that many of the great cities
took up arms against their nobles, who, formerly favoured by the emperor,
were oppressing them, whilst the Church was favouring them so as to gain
authority in temporal power: in many others their citizens became princes.
From this it came to pass that Italy fell partly into the hands of the
Church and of republics, and, the Church consisting of priests and the
republic of citizens unaccustomed to arms, both commenced to enlist foreigners.
The first who gave renown to this soldiery was Alberigo da Conio, a native
of the Romagna. From the school of this man sprang, among others, Braccio
and Sforza, who in their time were the arbiters of Italy. After these came
all the other captains who till now have directed the arms of Italy; and
the end of all their valour has been, that she has been overrun by Charles,
robbed by Louis, ravaged by Ferdinand, and insulted by the Switzers. The
principle that has guided them has been, first, to lower the credit of
infantry so that they might increase their own. They did this because,
subsisting on their pay and without territory, they were unable to support
many soldiers, and a few infantry did not give them any authority; so they
were led to employ cavalry, with a moderate force of which they were maintained
and honoured; and affairs were brought to such a pass that, in an army
of twenty thousand soldiers, there were not to be found two thousand foot
soldiers. They had, besides this, used every art to lessen fatigue and
danger to themselves and their soldiers, not killing in the fray, but taking
prisoners and liberating without ransom. They did not attack towns at night,
nor did the garrisons of the towns attack encampments at night; they did
not surround the camp either with stockade or ditch, nor did they campaign
in the winter. All these things were permitted by their military rules,
and devised by them to avoid, as I have said, both fatigue and dangers;
thus they have brought Italy to slavery and contempt.
CHAPTER 13
CONCERNING AUXILIARIES, MIXED SOLDIERY,
AND ONE'S OWN AUXILIARIES
AUXILIARIES, which are the other useless
arm, are employed when a prince is called in with his forces to aid and
defend, as was done by Pope Julius in the most recent times; for he, having,
in the enterprise against Ferrara, had poor proof of his mercenaries, turned
to auxiliaries, and stipulated with Ferdinand, King of Spain, for his assistance
with men and arms. These arms may be useful and good in themselves, but
for him who calls them in they are always disadvantageous; for losing,
one is undone, and winning, one is their captive. And although ancient
histories may be full of examples, I do not wish to leave this recent one
of Pope Julius II, the peril of which cannot fall to be perceived; for
he, wishing to get Ferrara, threw himself entirely into the hands of the
foreigner. But his good fortune brought about a third event, so that he
did not reap the fruit of his rash choice; because, having auxiliaries
routed at Ravenna, and the Switzers having risen and driven out the conquerors
(against all expectation, both his and others), it so came to pass that
he did not become prisoner to his enemies, they having fled, nor to his
auxiliaries, he having conquered by other arms than theirs. The Florentines,
being entirely without arms, sent ten thousand Frenchmen to take Pisa,
whereby they ran more danger than at any other time of their troubles.
The Emperor of Constantinople, to oppose his neighbours, sent ten thousand
Turks into Greece, who, on the war being finished, were not willing to
quit; this was the beginning of the servitude of Greece to the infidels.
Therefore, let him who has no desire to conquer make use of these arms,
for they are much more hazardous than mercenaries, because with them the
ruin is ready made; they are all united, all yield obedience to others;
but with mercenaries, when they have conquered, more time and better opportunities
are needed to injure you; they are not all of one community, they are found
and paid by you, and a third party, which you have made their head, is
not able all at once to assume enough authority to injure you. In conclusion,
in mercenaries dastardy is most dangerous; in auxiliaries, valour. The
wise prince, therefore, has always avoided these arms and turned to his
own; and has been willing rather to lose with them than to conquer with
others, not deeming that a real victory which is gained with the arms of
others. I shall never hesitate to cite Cesare Borgia and his actions. This
duke entered the Romagna with auxiliaries, taking there only French soldiers,
and with them he captured Imola and Forli; but afterwards, such forces
not appearing to him reliable, he turned to mercenaries, discerning less
danger in them, and enlisted the Orsini and Vitelli; whom presently, on
handling and finding them doubtful, unfaithful, and dangerous, he destroyed
and turned to his own men. And the difference between one and the other
of these forces can easily be seen when one considers the difference there
was in the reputation of the duke, when he had the French, when he had
the Orsini and Vitelli, and when he relied on his own soldiers, on whose
fidelity he could always count and found it ever increasing; he was never
esteemed more highly than when every one saw that he was complete master
of his own forces. I was not intending to go beyond Italian and recent
examples, but I am unwilling to leave out Hiero, the Syracusan, he being
one of those I have named above. This man, as I have said, made head of
the army by the Syracusans, soon found out that a mercenary soldiery, constituted
like our Italian condottieri, was of no use; and it appearing to him that
he could neither keep them nor let them go, he had them all cut to pieces,
and afterwards made war with his own forces and not with aliens. I wish
also to recall to memory an instance from the Old Testament applicable
to this subject. David offered himself to Saul to fight with Goliath, the
Philistine champion, and, to give him courage, Saul armed him with his
own weapons; which David rejected as soon as he had them on his back, saying
he could make no use of them, and that he wished to meet the enemy with
his sling and his knife. In conclusion, the arms of others either fall
from your back, or they weigh you down, or they bind you fast. Charles
VII, the father of King Louis XI, having by good fortune and valour liberated
France from the English, recognized the necessity of being armed with forces
of his own, and he established in his kingdom ordinances concerning men-at-arms
and infantry. Afterwards his son, King Louis, abolished the infantry and
began to enlist the Switzers, which mistake, followed by others, is, as
is now seen, a source of peril to that kingdom; because, having raised
the reputation of the Switzers, he has entirely diminished the value of
his own arms, for he has destroyed the infantry altogether; and his men-at-arms
he has subordinated to others, for, being as they are so accustomed to
fight along with Switzers, it does not appear that they can now conquer
without them. Hence it arises that the French cannot stand against the
Switzers, and without the Switzers they do not come off well against others.
The armies of the French have thus become mixed, partly mercenary and partly
national, both of which arms together are much better than mercenaries
alone or auxiliaries alone, yet much inferior to one's own forces. And
this example proves it, the kingdom of France would be unconquerable if
the ordinance of Charles had been enlarged or maintained. But the scanty
wisdom of man, on entering into an affair which looks well at first, cannot
discern the poison that is hidden in it, as I have said above of hectic
fevers. Therefore, if he who rules a principality cannot recognize evils
until they are upon him, he is not truly wise; and this insight is given
to few. And if the first disaster to the Roman Empire should be examined,
it will be found to have commenced only with the enlisting of the Goths;
because from that time the vigour of the Roman Empire began to decline,
and all that valour which had raised it passed away to others. I conclude,
therefore, that no principality is secure without having its own forces;
on the contrary, it is entirely dependent on good fortune, not having the
valour which in adversity would defend it. And it has always been the opinion
and judgment of wise men that nothing can be so uncertain or unstable as
fame or power not founded on its own strength. And one's own forces are
those which are composed either of subjects, citizens, or dependants; all
others are mercenaries or auxiliaries. And the way to take ready one's
own forces will be easily found if the rules suggested by me shall be reflected
upon, and if one will consider how Philip, the father of Alexander the
Great, and many republics and princes have armed and organized themselves,
to which rules I entirely commit myself.
CHAPTER 14
THAT WHICH CONCERNS A PRINCE ON THE
SUBJECT OF THE ART OF WAR
A PRINCE ought to have no other aim
or thought, nor select anything else for his study, than war and its rules
and discipline; for this is the sole art that belongs to him who rules,
and it is of such force that it not only upholds those who are born princes,
but it often enables men to rise from a private station to that rank. And,
on the contrary, it is seen that when princes have thought more of ease
than of arms they have lost their states. And the first cause of your losing
it is to neglect this art; and what enables you to acquire a state is to
be master of the art. Francesco Sforza, through being martial, from a private
person became Duke of Milan; and the sons, through avoiding the hardships
and troubles of arms, from dukes became private persons. For among other
evils which being unarmed brings you, it causes you to be despised, and
this is one of those ignominies against which a prince ought to guard himself,
as is shown later on. Because there is nothing proportionate between the
armed and the unarmed; and it is not reasonable that he who is armed should
yield obedience willingly to him who is unarmed, or that the unarmed man
should be secure among armed servants. Because, there being in the one
disdain and in the other suspicion, it is not possible for them to work
well together. And therefore a prince who does not understand the art of
war, over and above the other misfortunes already mentioned, cannot be
respected by his soldiers, nor can he rely on them. He ought never, therefore,
to have out of his thoughts this subject of war, and in peace he should
addict himself more to its exercise than in war; this he can do in two
ways, the one by action, the other by study. As regards action, he ought
above all things to keep his men well organized and drilled, to follow
incessantly the chase, by which he accustoms his body to hardships, and
learns something of the nature of localities, and gets to find out how
the mountains rise, how the valleys open out, how the plains lie, and to
understand the nature of rivers and marshes, and in all this to take the
greatest care. Which knowledge is useful in two ways. Firstly, he learns
to know his country, and is better able to undertake its defence; afterwards,
by means of the knowledge and observation of that locality, he understands
with ease any other which it may be necessary for him to study hereafter;
because the hills, valleys, and plains, and rivers and marshes that are,
for instance, in Tuscany, have a certain resemblance to those of other
countries, so that with a knowledge of the aspect of one country one can
easily arrive at a knowledge of others. And the prince that lacks this
skill lacks the essential which it is desirable that a captain should possess,
for it teaches him to surprise his enemy, to select quarters, to lead armies,
to array the battle, to besiege towns to advantage. Philopoemen, Prince
of the Achaeans, among other praises which writers have bestowed on him,
is commended because in time of peace he never had anything in his mind
but the rules of war; and when he was in the country with friends, he often
stopped and reasoned with them: "If the enemy should be upon that hill,
and we should find ourselves here with our army, with whom would be the
advantage? How should one best advance to meet him, keeping the ranks?
If we should wish to retreat, how ought we to set about it? If they should
retreat, how ought we to pursue?" And he would set forth to them, as he
went, all the chances that could befall an army; he would listen to their
opinion and state his, confirming it with reasons, so that by these continual
discussions there could never arise, in time of war, any unexpected circumstances
that he could deal with. But to exercise the intellect the prince should
read histories, and study there the actions of illustrious men, to see
how they have borne themselves in war, to examine the causes of their victories
and defeat, so as to avoid the latter and imitate the former; and above
all do as an illustrious man did, who took as an exemplar one who had been
praised and famous before him, and whose achievements and deeds he always
kept in his mind, as it is said Alexander the Great imitated Achilles,
Caesar Alexander, Scipio Cyrus. And whoever reads the life of Cyrus, written
by Xenophon, will recognize afterwards in the life of Scipio how that imitation
was his glory, and how in chastity, affability, humanity, and liberality
Scipio conformed to those things which have been written of Cyrus by Xenophon.
A wise prince ought to observe some such rules, and never in peaceful times
stand idle, but increase his resources with industry in such a way that
they may be available to him in adversity, so that if fortune changes it
may find him prepared to resist her blows.
CHAPTER 15
CONCERNING THINGS FOR WHICH MEN, AND
ESPECIALLY PRINCES, ARE PRAISED OR BLAMED
IT REMAINS now to see what ought to
be the rules of conduct for a prince towards subject and friends. And as
I know that many have written on this point, I expect I shall be considered
presumptuous in mentioning it again, especially as in discussing it I shall
depart from the methods of other people. But, it being my intention to
write a thing which shall be useful to him who apprehends it, it appears
to me more appropriate to follow up the real truth of a matter than the
imagination of it; for many have pictured republics and principalities
which in fact have never been known or seen, because how one lives is so
far distant from how one ought to live, that he who neglects what is done
for what ought to be done, sooner effects his ruin than his preservation;
for a man who wishes to act entirely up to his professions of virtue soon
meets with what destroys him among so much that is evil. Hence it is necessary
for a prince wishing to hold his own to know how to do wrong, and to make
use of it or not according to necessity. Therefore, putting on one side
imaginary things concerning a prince, and discussing those which are real,
I say that all men when they are spoken of, and chiefly princes for being
more highly placed, are remarkable for some of those qualities which bring
them either blame or praise; and thus it is that one is reputed liberal,
another miserly, using a Tuscan term (because an avaricious person in our
language is still he who desires to possess by robbery, whilst we call
one miserly who deprives himself too much of the use of his own); one is
reputed generous, one rapacious; one cruel, one compassionate; one faithless,
another faithful; one effeminate and cowardly, another bold and brave;
one affable, another haughty; one lascivious, another chaste; one sincere,
another cunning; one hard, another easy; one grave, another frivolous;
one religious, another unbelieving, and the like. And I know that every
one will confess that it would be most praiseworthy in a prince to exhibit
all the above qualities that are considered good; but because they can
neither be entirely possessed nor observed, for human conditions do not
permit it, it is necessary for him to be sufficiently prudent that he may
know how to avoid the reproach of those vices which would lose him his
state; and also to keep himself, if it be possible, from those which would
not lose him it; but this not being possible, he may with less hesitation
abandon himself to them. And again, he need not make himself uneasy at
incurring a reproach for those vices without which the state can only be
saved with difficulty, for if everything is considered carefully, it will
be found that something which looks like virtue, if followed, would be
his ruin; whilst something else, which looks like vice, yet followed brings
him security and prosperity.
CHAPTER 16
CONCERNING LIBERALITY AND MEANNESS
COMMENCING then with the first of the
above-named characteristics, I say that it would be well to be reputed
liberal. Nevertheless, liberality exercised in a way that does not bring
you the reputation for it, injures you; for if one exercises it honestly
and as it should be exercised, it may not become known, and you will not
avoid the reproach of its opposite. Therefore, any one wishing to maintain
among men the name of liberal is obliged to avoid no attribute of magnificence;
so that a prince thus inclined will consume in such acts all his property,
and will be compelled in the end, if he wish to maintain the name of liberal,
to unduly weigh down his people, and tax them, and do everything he can
to get money. This will soon make him odious to his subjects, and becoming
poor he will be little valued by any one; thus, with his liberality, having
offended many and rewarded few, he is affected by the very first trouble
and imperilled by whatever may be the first danger; recognizing this himself,
and wishing to draw back from it, he runs at once into the reproach of
being miserly. Therefore, a prince, not being able to exercise this virtue
of liberality in such a way that it is recognized, except to his cost,
if he is wise he ought not to fear the reputation of being mean, for in
time he will come to be more considered than if liberal, seeing that with
his economy his revenues are enough, that he can defend himself against
all attacks, and is able to engage in enterprises without burdening his
people; thus it comes to pass that he exercises liberality towards all
from whom he does not take, who are numberless, and meanness towards those
to whom he does not give, who are few. We have not seen great things done
in our time except by those who have been considered mean; the rest have
failed. Pope Julius the Second was assisted in reaching the papacy by a
reputation for liberality, yet he did not strive afterwards to keep it
up, when he made war on the King of France; and he made many wars without
imposing any extraordinary tax on his subjects, for he supplied his additional
expenses out of his long thriftiness. The present King of Spain would not
have undertaken or conquered in so many enterprises if he had been reputed
liberal. A prince, therefore, provided that he has not to rob his subjects,
that he can defend himself, that he does not become poor and abject, that
he is not forced to become rapacious, ought to hold of little account a
reputation for being mean, for it is one of those vices which will enable
him to govern. And if any one should say: Caesar obtained empire by liberality,
and many others have reached the highest positions by having been liberal,
and by being considered so, I answer: Either you are a prince in fact,
or in a way to become one. In the first case this liberality is dangerous,
in the second it is very necessary to be considered liberal; and Caesar
was one of those who wished to become pre-eminent in Rome; but if he had
survived after becoming so, and had not moderated his expenses, he would
have destroyed his government. And if any one should reply: Many have been
princes, and have done great things with armies, who have been considered
very liberal, I reply: Either a prince spends that which is his own or
his subjects' or else that of others. In the first case he ought to be
sparing, in the second he ought not to neglect any opportunity for liberality.
And to the price who goes forth with his army, supporting it by pillage,
sack, and extortion, handling that which belongs to others, this liberality
is necessary, otherwise he would not be followed by soldiers. And of that
which is neither yours nor your subjects' you can be a ready giver, as
were Cyrus, Caesar, and Alexander; because it does not take away your reputation
if you squander that of others, but adds to it; it is only squandering
your own that injures you. And there is nothing wastes so rapidly as liberality,
for even whilst you exercise it you lose the power to do so, and so become
either poor or despised, or else, in avoiding poverty, rapacious and hated.
And a prince should guard himself, above all things, against being despised
and hated; and liberality leads you to both. Therefore it is wiser to have
a reputation for meanness which brings reproach without hatred, than to
be compelled through seeking a reputation for liberality to incur a name
for rapacity which begets reproach with hatred.
CHAPTER 17
CONCERNING CRUELTY AND CLEMENCY, AND
WHETHER IT IS BETTER TO BE LOVED THAN FEARED
COMING now to the other qualities mentioned
above, I say that every prince ought to desire to be considered clement
and not cruel. Nevertheless he ought to take care not to misuse this clemency.
Cesare Borgia was considered cruel; notwithstanding, his cruelty reconciled
the Romagna, unified it, and restored it to peace and loyalty. And if this
be rightly considered, he will be seen to have been much more merciful
than the Florentine people, who, to avoid a reputation for cruelty, permitted
Pistoia to be destroyed. Therefore a prince, so long as he keeps his subjects
united and loyal, ought not to mind the reproach of cruelty; because with
a few examples he will be more merciful than those who, through too much
mercy, allow disorders to arise, from which follow murders or robberies;
for these are wont to injure the whole people, whilst those executions
which originate with a prince offend the individual only. And of all princes,
it is impossible for the new prince to avoid the imputation of cruelty,
owing to new states being full of dangers. Hence Virgil, through the mouth
of Dido, excuses the inhumanity of her reign owing to its being new, saying:
Res dura, et regni novitas me talia cogunt Moliri, et late fines custode
tueri.* * ...against my will, my fate, A throne unsettled, and an infant
state, Bid me defend my realms with all my pow'rs, And guard with these
severities my shores. Nevertheless he ought to be slow to believe and to
act, nor should he himself show fear, but proceed in a temperate manner
with prudence and humanity, so that too much confidence may not make him
incautious and too much distrust render him intolerable. Upon this a question
arises: whether it be better to be loved than feared or feared than loved?
It may be answered that one should wish to be both, but, because it is
difficult to unite them in one person, is much safer to be feared than
loved, when, of the two, either must be dispensed with. Because this is
to be asserted in general of men, that they are ungrateful, fickle, false,
cowardly, covetous, and as long as you succeed they are yours entirely;
they will offer you their blood, property, life and children, as is said
above, when the need is far distant; but when it approaches they turn against
you. And that prince who, relying entirely on their promises, has neglected
other precautions, is ruined; because friendships that are obtained by
payments, and not by greatness or nobility of mind, may indeed be earned,
but they are not secured, and in time of need cannot be relied upon; and
men have less scruple in offending one who is beloved than one who is feared,
for love is preserved by the link of obligation which, owing to the baseness
of men, is broken at every opportunity for their advantage; but fear preserves
you by a dread of punishment which never fails. Nevertheless a prince ought
to inspire fear in such a way that, if he does not win love, he avoids
hatred; because he can endure very well being feared whilst he is not hated,
which will always be as long as he abstains from the property of his citizens
and subjects and from their women. But when it is necessary for him to
proceed against the life of someone, he must do it on proper justification
and for manifest cause, but above all things he must keep his hands off
the property of others, because men more quickly forget the death of their
father than the loss of their patrimony. Besides, pretexts for taking away
the property are never wanting; for he who has once begun to live by robbery
will always find pretexts for seizing what belongs to others; but reasons
for taking life, on the contrary, are more difficult to find and sooner
lapse. But when a prince is with his army, and has under control a multitude
of soldiers, then it is quite necessary for him to disregard the reputation
of cruelty, for without it he would never hold his army united or disposed
to its duties. Among the wonderful deeds of Hannibal this one is enumerated:
that having led an enormous army, composed of many various races of men,
to fight in foreign lands, no dissensions arose either among them or against
the prince, whether in his bad or in his good fortune. This arose from
nothing else than his inhuman cruelty, which, with his boundless valour,
made him revered and terrible in the sight of his soldiers, but without
that cruelty, his other virtues were not sufficient to produce this effect.
And shortsighted writers admire his deeds from one point of view and from
another condemn the principal cause of them. That it is true his other
virtues would not have been sufficient for him may be proved by the case
of Scipio, that most excellent man, not of his own times but within the
memory of man, against whom, nevertheless, his army rebelled in Spain;
this arose from nothing but his too great forbearance, which gave his soldiers
more licence than is consistent with military discipline. For this he was
upbraided in the Senate by Fabius Maximus, and called the corrupter of
the Roman soldiery. The Locrians were laid waste by a legate of Scipio,
yet they were not avenged by him, nor was the insolence of the legate punished,
owing entirely to his easy nature. Insomuch that someone in the Senate,
wishing to excuse him, said there were many men who knew much better how
not to err than to correct the errors of others. This disposition, if he
had been continued in the command, would have destroyed in time the fame
and glory of Scipio; but, he being under the control of the Senate, this
injurious characteristic not only concealed itself, but contributed to
his glory. Returning to the question of being feared or loved, I come to
the conclusion that, men loving according to their own will and fearing
according to that of the prince, a wise prince should establish himself
on that which is in his own control and not in that of others; he must
endeavour only to avoid hatred, as is noted.
CHAPTER 18
CONCERNING THE WAY IN WHICH PRINCES
SHOULD KEEP FAITH
EVERY one admits how praiseworthy it
is in a prince to keep faith, and to live with integrity and not with craft.
Nevertheless our experience has been that those princes who have done great
things have held good faith of little account, and have known how to circumvent
the intellect of men by craft, and in the end have overcome those who have
relied on their word. You must know there are two ways of contesting, the
one by the law, the other by force; the first method is proper to men,
the second to beasts; but because the first is frequently not sufficient,
it is necessary to have recourse to the second. Therefore it is necessary
for a prince to understand how to avail himself of the beast and the man.
This has been figuratively taught to princes by ancient writers, who describe
how Achilles and many other princes of old were given to the Centaur Chiron
to nurse, who brought them up in his discipline; which means solely that,
as they had for a teacher one who was half beast and half man, so it is
necessary for a prince to know how to make use of both natures, and that
one without the other is not durable. A prince, therefore, being compelled
knowingly to adopt the beast, ought to choose the fox and the lion; because
the lion cannot defend himself against snares and the fox cannot defend
himself against wolves. Therefore, it is necessary to be a fox to discover
the snares and a lion to terrify the wolves. Those who rely simply on the
lion do not understand what they are about. Therefore a wise lord cannot,
nor ought he to, keep faith when such observance may be turned against
him, and when the reasons that caused him to pledge it exist no longer.
If men were entirely good this precept would not hold, but because they
are bad, and will not keep faith with you, you too are not bound to observe
it with them. Nor will there ever be wanting to a prince legitimate reasons
to excuse this nonobservance. Of this endless modern examples could be
given, showing how many treaties and engagements have been made void and
of no effect through the faithlessness of princes; and he who has known
best how to employ the fox has succeeded best. But it is necessary to know
well how to disguise this characteristic, and to be a great pretender and
dissembler; and men are so simple, and so subject to present necessities,
that he who seeks to deceive will always find someone who will allow himself
to be deceived. One recent example I cannot pass over in silence. Alexander
VI did nothing else but deceive men, nor ever thought of doing otherwise,
and he always found victims; for there never was a man who had greater
power in asserting, or who with greater oaths would affirm a thing, yet
would observe it less; nevertheless his deceits always succeeded according
to his wishes, because he well understood this side of mankind. Therefore
it is unnecessary for a prince to have all the good qualities I have enumerated,
but it is very necessary to appear to have them. And I shall dare to say
this also, that to have them and always to observe them is injurious, and
that to appear to have them is useful; to appear merciful, faithful, humane,
religious, upright, and to be so, but with a mind so framed that should
you require not to be so, you may be able and know how to change to the
opposite. And you have to understand this, that a prince, especially a
new one, cannot observe all those things for which men are esteemed, being
often forced, in order to maintain the state, to act contrary to faith,
friendship, humanity, and religion. Therefore it is necessary for him to
have a mind ready to turn itself accordingly as the winds and variations
of fortune force it, yet, as I have said above, not to diverge from the
good if he can avoid doing so, but, if compelled, then to know how to set
about it. For this reason a prince ought to take care that he never lets
anything slip from his lips that is not replete with the above-named five
qualities, that he may appear to him who sees and hears him altogether
merciful, faithful, humane, upright, and religious. There is nothing more
necessary to appear to have than this last quality, inasmuch as men judge
generally more by the eye than by the hand, because it belongs to everybody
to see you, to few to come in touch with you. Every one sees what you appear
to be, few really know what you are, and those few dare not oppose themselves
to the opinion of the many, who have the majesty of the state to defend
them; and in the actions of all men, and especially of princes, which it
is not prudent to challenge, one judges by the result. For that reason,
let a prince have the credit of conquering and holding his state, the means
will always be considered honest, and he will be praised by everybody because
the vulgar are always taken by what a thing seems to be and by what comes
of it; and in the world there are only the vulgar, for the few find a place
there only when the many have no ground to rest on. One prince of the present
time, whom it is not well to name, never preaches anything else but peace
and good faith, and to both he is most hostile, and either, if he had kept
it, would have deprived him of reputation and kingdom many a time.
Maximilian I, Holy Roman Emperor.
CHAPTER 19
THAT ONE SHOULD AVOID BEING DESPISED
AND HATED
NOW, concerning the characteristics
of which mention is made above, I have spoken of the more important ones,
the others I wish to discuss briefly under this generality, that the prince
must consider, as has been in part said before, how to avoid those things
which will make him hated or contemptible; and as often as he shall have
succeeded he will have fulfilled his part, and he need not fear any danger
in other reproaches. It makes him hated above all things, as I have said,
to be rapacious, and to be a violator of the property and women of his
subjects, from both of which he must abstain. And when neither their property
nor honour is touched, the majority of men live content, and he has only
to contend with the ambition of a few, whom he can curb with ease in many
ways. It makes him contemptible to be considered fickle, frivolous, effeminate,
mean-spirited, irresolute, from all of which a prince should guard himself
as from a rock; and he should endeavour to show in his actions greatness,
courage, gravity, and fortitude; and in his private dealings with his subjects
let him show that his judgments are irrevocable, and maintain himself in
such reputation that no one can hope either to deceive him or to get round
him. That prince is highly esteemed who conveys this impression of himself,
and he who is highly esteemed is not easily conspired against; for, provided
it is well known that he is an excellent man and revered by his people,
he can only be attacked with difficulty. For this reason a prince ought
to have two fears, one from within, on account of his subjects, the other
from without, on account of external powers. From the latter he is defended
by being well armed and having good allies, and if he is well armed he
will have good friends, and affairs will always remain quiet within when
they are quiet without, unless they should have been already disturbed
by conspiracy; and even should affairs outside be disturbed, if he has
carried out his preparations and has lived as I have said, as long as he
does not despair, he will resist every attack, as I said Nabis the Spartan
did. But concerning his subjects, when affairs outside are disturbed he
has only to fear that they will conspire secretly, from which a prince
can easily secure himself by avoiding being hated and despised, and by
keeping the people satisfied with him, which it is most necessary for him
to accomplish, as I said above at length. And one of the most efficacious
remedies that a prince can have against conspiracies is not to be hated
and despised by the people, for he who conspires against a prince always
expects to please them by his removal; but when the conspirator can only
look forward to offending them, he will not have the courage to take such
a course, for the difficulties that confront a conspirator are infinite.
And as experience shows, many have been the conspiracies, but few have
been successful; because he who conspires cannot act alone, nor can he
take a companion except from those whom he believes to be malcontents,
and as soon as you have opened your mind to a malcontent you have given
him the material with which to content himself, for by denouncing you he
can look for every advantage; so that, seeing the gain from this course
to be assured, and seeing the other to be doubtful and full of dangers,
he must be a very rare friend, or a thoroughly obstinate enemy of the prince,
to keep faith with you. And, to reduce the matter into a small compass,
I say that, on the side of the conspirator, there is nothing but fear,
jealousy, prospect of punishment to terrify him; but on the side of the
prince there is the majesty of the principality, the laws, the protection
of friends and the state to defend him; so that, adding to all these things
the popular goodwill, it is impossible that any one should be so rash as
to conspire. For whereas in general the conspirator has to fear before
the execution of his plot, in this case he has also to fear the sequel
to the crime; because on account of it he has the people for an enemy,
and thus cannot hope for any escape. Endless examples could be given on
this subject, but I will be content with one, brought to pass within the
memory of our fathers. Messer Annibale Bentivoglio, who was prince in Bologna
(grandfather of the present Annibale), having been murdered by the Canneschi,
who had conspired against him, not one of his family survived but Messer
Giovanni, who was in childhood: immediately after his assassination the
people rose and murdered all the Canneschi. This sprung from the popular
goodwill which the house of Bentivoglio enjoyed in those days in Bologna;
which was so great that, although none remained there after the death of
Annibale who were able to rule the state, the Bolognese, having information
that there was one of the Bentivoglio family in Florence, who up to that
time had been considered the son of a blacksmith, sent to Florence for
him and gave him the government of their city, and it was ruled by him
until Messer Giovanni came in due course to the government. For this reason
I consider that a prince ought to reckon conspiracies of little account
when his people hold him in esteem; but when it is hostile to him, and
bears hatred towards him, he ought to fear everything and everybody. And
well-ordered states and wise princes have taken every care not to drive
the nobles to desperation, and to keep the people satisfied and contented,
for this is one of the most important objects a prince can have. Among
the best ordered and governed kingdoms of our times is France, and in it
are found many good institutions on which depend the liberty and security
of the king; of these the first is the parliament and its authority, because
he who founded the kingdom, knowing the ambition of the nobility and their
boldness, considered that a bit in their mouths would be necessary to hold
them in; and, on the other side, knowing the hatred of the people, founded
in fear, against the nobles, he wished to protect them, yet he was not
anxious for this to be the particular care of the king; therefore, to take
away the reproach which he would be liable to from the nobles for favouring
the people, and from the people for favouring the nobles, he set up an
arbiter, who should be one who could beat down the great and favour the
lesser without reproach to the king. Neither could you have a better or
a more prudent arrangement, or a greater source of security to the king
and kingdom. From this one can draw another important conclusion, that
princes ought to leave affairs of reproach to the management of others,
and keep those of grace in their own hands. And further, I consider that
a prince ought to cherish the nobles, but not so as to make himself hated
by the people. It may appear, perhaps, to some who have examined the lives
and deaths of the Roman emperors that many of them would be an example
contrary to my opinion, seeing that some of them lived nobly and showed
great qualities of soul, nevertheless they have lost their empire or have
been killed by subjects who have conspired against them. Wishing, therefore,
to answer these objections, I will recall the characters of some of the
emperors, and will show that the causes of their ruin were not different
to those alleged by me; at the same time I will only submit for consideration
those things that are noteworthy to him who studies the affairs of those
times. It seems to me sufficient to take all those emperors who succeeded
to the empire from Marcus the philosopher down to Maximinus; they were
Marcus and his son Commodus, Pertinax, Julian, Severus and his son Antoninus
Caracalla, Macrinus, Heliogabalus, Alexander, and Maximinus. There is first
to note that, whereas in other principalities the ambition of the nobles
and the insolence of the people only have to be contended with, the Roman
emperors had a third difficulty in having to put up with the cruelty and
avarice of their soldiers, a matter so beset with difficulties that it
was the ruin of many; for it was a hard thing to give satisfaction both
to soldiers and people; because the people loved peace, and for this reason
they loved the unaspiring prince, whilst the soldiers loved the warlike
prince who was bold, cruel, and rapacious, which qualities they were quite
willing he should exercise upon the people, so that they could get double
pay and give vent to their greed and cruelty. Hence it arose that those
emperors were always overthrown who, either by birth or training, had no
great authority, and most of them, especially those who came new to the
principality, recognizing the difficulty of these two opposing humours,
were inclined to give satisfaction to the soldiers, caring little about
injuring the people. Which course was necessary, because, as princes cannot
help being hated by someone, they ought, in the first place, to avoid being
hated by every one, and when they cannot compass this, they ought to endeavour
with the utmost diligence to avoid the hatred of the most powerful. Therefore,
those emperors who through inexperience had need of special favour adhered
more readily to the soldiers than to the people; a course which turned
out advantageous to them or not, accordingly as the prince knew how to
maintain authority over them. From these causes it arose that Marcus, [Aurelius],
Pertinax, and Alexander, being all men of modest life, lovers of justice,
enemies to cruelty, humane, and benignant, came to a sad end except Marcus;
he alone lived and died honoured, because he had succeeded to the throne
by hereditary title, and owed nothing either to the soldiers or the people;
and afterwards, being possessed of many virtues which made him respected,
he always kept both orders in their places whilst he lived, and was neither
hated nor despised. But Pertinax was created emperor against the wishes
of the soldiers, who, being accustomed to live licentiously under Commodus,
could not endure the honest life to which Pertinax wished to reduce them;
thus, having given cause for hatred, to which hatred there was added contempt
for his old age, he was overthrown at the very beginning of his administration.
And here it should be noted that hatred is acquired as much by good works
as by bad ones, therefore, as I said before, a prince wishing to keep his
state is very often forced to do evil; for when that body is corrupt whom
you think you have need of to maintain yourself- it may be either the people
or the soldiers or the nobles- you have to submit to its humours and to
gratify them, and then good works will do you harm. But let us come to
Alexander, who was a man of such great goodness, that among the other praises
which are accorded him is this, that in the fourteen years he held the
empire no one was ever put to death by him unjudged; nevertheless, being
considered effeminate and a man who allowed himself to be governed by his
mother, he became despised, the army conspired against him, and murdered
him. Turning now to the opposite characters of Commodus, Severus, Antoninus
Caracalla, and Maximinus, you will find them all cruel and rapacious- men
who, to satisfy their soldiers, did not hesitate to commit every kind of
iniquity against the people; and all, except Severus, came to a bad end;
but in Severus there was so much valour that, keeping the soldiers friendly,
although the people were oppressed by him, he reigned successfully; for
his valour made him so much admired in the sight of the soldiers and people
that the latter were kept in a way astonished and awed and the former respectful
and satisfied. And because the actions of this man, as a new prince, were
great, I wish to show briefly that he knew well how to counterfeit the
fox and the lion, which natures, as I said above, it is necessary for a
prince to imitate. Knowing the sloth of the Emperor Julian, he persuaded
the army in Sclavonia, of which he was captain, that it would be right
to go to Rome and avenge the death of Pertinax, who had been killed by
the praetorian soldiers; and under this pretext, without appearing to aspire
to the throne, he moved the army on Rome, and reached Italy before it was
known that he had started. On his arrival at Rome, the Senate, through
fear, elected him emperor and killed Julian. After this there remained
for Severus, who wished to make himself master of the whole empire, two
difficulties; one in Asia, where Niger, head of the Asiatic army, had caused
himself to be proclaimed emperor; the other in the west where Albinus was,
who also aspired to the throne. And as he considered it dangerous to declare
himself hostile to both, he decided to attack Niger and to deceive Albinus.
To the latter he wrote that, being elected emperor by the Senate, he was
willing to share that dignity with him and sent him the title of Caesar;
and, moreover, that the Senate had made Albinus his colleague; which things
were accepted by Albinus as true. But after Severus had conquered and killed
Niger, and settled oriental affairs, he returned to Rome and complained
to the Senate that Albinus, little recognizing the benefits that he had
received from him, had by treachery sought to murder him, and for this
ingratitude he was compelled to punish him. Afterwards he sought him out
in France, and took from him his government and life. He who will, therefore,
carefully examine the actions of this man will find him a most valiant
lion and a most cunning fox; he will find him feared and respected by every
one, and not hated by the army; and it need not be wondered at that he,
the new man, well, because his supreme renown always protected him from
that hatred which the people might have conceived against him for his violence.
But his son Antoninus was a most eminent man, and had very excellent qualities,
which made him admirable in the sight of the people and acceptable to the
soldiers, for he was a warlike man, most enduring of fatigue, a despiser
of all delicate food and other luxuries, which caused him to be beloved
by the armies. Nevertheless, his ferocity and cruelties were so great and
so unheard of that, after endless single murders, he killed a large number
of the people of Rome and all those of Alexandria. He became hated by the
whole world, and also feared by those he had around him, to such an extent
that he was murdered in the midst of his army by a centurion. And here
it must be noted that such-like deaths, which are deliberately inflicted
with a resolved and desperate courage, cannot be avoided by princes, because
any one who does not fear to die can inflict them; but a prince may fear
them the less because they are very rare; he has only to be careful not
to do any grave injury to those whom he employs or has around him in the
service of the state. Antoninus had not taken this care, but had contumeliously
killed a brother of that centurion, whom also he daily threatened, yet
retained in his bodyguard; which, as it turned out, was a rash thing to
do, and proved the emperor's ruin. But let us come to Commodus, to whom
it should have been very easy to hold the empire, for, being the son of
Marcus, he had inherited it, and he had only to follow in the footsteps
of his father to please his people and soldiers; but, being by nature cruel
and brutal, he gave himself up to amusing the soldiers and corrupting them,
so that he might indulge his rapacity upon the people; on the other hand,
not maintaining his dignity, often descending to the theatre to compete
with gladiators, and doing other vile things, little worthy of the imperial
majesty, he fell into contempt with the soldiers, and being hated by one
party and despised by the other, he was conspired against and killed. It
remains to discuss the character of Maximinus. He was a very warlike man,
and the armies, being disgusted with the effeminacy of Alexander, of whom
I have already spoken, killed him and elected Maximinus to the throne.
This he did not possess for long, for two things made him hated and despised;
the one, his having kept sheep in Thrace, which brought him into contempt
(it being well known to all, and considered a great indignity by every
one), and the other, his having at the accession to his dominions deferred
going to Rome and taking possession of the imperial seat; he had also gained
a reputation for the utmost ferocity by having, through his prefects in
Rome and elsewhere in the empire, practised many cruelties, so that the
whole world was moved to anger at the meanness of his birth and to fear
at his barbarity. First Africa rebelled, then the Senate with all the people
of Rome, and all Italy conspired against him, to which may be added his
own army: this latter, besieging Aquileia and meeting with difficulties
in taking it, were disgusted with his cruelties, and fearing him less when
they found so many against him, murdered him. I do not wish to discuss
Heliogabalus, Macrinus, or Julian, who, being thoroughly contemptible,
were quickly wiped out; but I will bring this discourse to a conclusion
by saying that princes in our times have this difficulty of giving inordinate
satisfaction to their soldiers in a far less degree, because, notwithstanding
one has to give them some indulgence, that is soon done; none of these
princes have armies that are veterans in the governance and administration
of provinces, as were the armies of the Roman Empire; and whereas it was
then more necessary to give satisfaction to the soldiers than to the people,
it is now more necessary to all princes, except the Turk and the Soldan,
to satisfy the people rather than the soldiers, because the people are
the more powerful. From the above I have excepted the Turk, who always
keeps round him twelve infantry and fifteen thousand cavalry on which depend
the security and strength of the kingdom, and it is necessary that, putting
aside every consideration for the people, he should keep them his friends.
The kingdom of the Soldan is similar; being entirely in the hands of soldiers,
follows again that, without regard to the people, he must keep them his
friends. But you must note that the state of the Soldan is unlike all other
principalities, for the reason that it is like the Christian pontificate,
which cannot be called either an hereditary or a newly formed principality;
because the sons of the old prince not the heirs, but he who is elected
to that position by those who have authority, and the sons remain only
noblemen. And this being an ancient custom, it cannot be called a new principality,
because there are none of those difficulties in it that are met with in
new ones; for although the prince is new, the constitution of the state
is old, and it is framed so as to receive him as if he were its hereditary
lord. But returning to the subject of our discourse, I say that whoever
will consider it will acknowledge that either hatred or contempt has been
fatal to the above-named emperors, and it will be recognized also how it
happened that, a number of them acting in one way and a number in another,
only one in each way came to a happy end and the rest to unhappy ones.
Because it would have been useless and dangerous for Pertinax and Alexander,
being new princes, to imitate Marcus, who was heir to the principality;
and likewise it would have been utterly destructive to Caracalla, Commodus,
and Maximinus to have imitated Severus, they not having sufficient valour
to enable them to tread in his footsteps. Therefore a prince, new to the
principality, cannot imitate the actions of Marcus, nor, again, is it necessary
to follow those of Severus, but he ought to take from Severus those parts
which are necessary to found his state, and from Marcus those which are
proper and glorious to keep a state that may already be stable and firm.
CHAPTER 20
ARE FORTRESSES, AND MANY OTHER THINGS
TO WHICH PRINCES OFTEN RESORT, ADVANTAGEOUS OR HURTFUL?
1. SOME princes, so as to hold securely
the state, have disarmed their subjects; others have kept their subject
towns by factions; others have fostered enmities against themselves; others
have laid themselves out to gain over those whom they distrusted in the
beginning of their governments; some have built fortresses; some have overthrown
and destroyed them. And although one cannot give a final judgment on all
one of these things unless one possesses the particulars of those states
in which a decision has to be made, nevertheless I will speak as comprehensively
as the matter of itself will admit.
2. There never was a new prince who
has disarmed his subjects; rather when he has found them disarmed he has
always armed them, because, by arming them, those arms become yours, those
men who were distrusted become faithful, and those who were faithful are
kept so, and your subjects become your adherents. And whereas all subjects
cannot be armed, yet when those whom you do arm are benefited, the others
can be handled more freely, and this difference in their treatment, which
they quite understand, makes the former your dependants, and the latter,
considering it to be necessary that those who have the most danger and
service should have the most reward, excuse you. But when you disarm them,
you at once offend them by showing that you distrust them, either for cowardice
or for want of loyalty, and either of these opinions breeds hatred against
you. And because you cannot remain unarmed, it follows that you turn to
mercenaries, which are of the character already shown; even if they should
be good they would not be sufficient to defend you against powerful enemies
and distrusted subjects. Therefore, as I have said, a new prince in a new
principality has always distributed arms. Histories are full of examples.
But when a prince acquires a new state, which he adds as a province to
his old one, then it is necessary to disarm the men of that state, except
those who have been his adherents in acquiring it; and these again, with
time and opportunity, should be rendered soft and effeminate; and matters
should be managed in such a way that all the armed men in the state shall
be your own soldiers who in your old state were living near you.
3. Our forefathers, and those who
were reckoned wise, were accustomed to say that it was necessary to hold
Pistoia by factions and Pisa by fortresses; and with this idea they fostered
quarrels in some of their tributary towns so as to keep possession of them
the more easily. This may have been well enough in those times when Italy
was in a way balanced, but I do not believe that it can be accepted as
a precept for to-day, because I do not believe that factions can ever be
of use; rather it is certain that when the enemy comes upon you in divided
cities you are quickly lost, because the weakest party will always assist
the outside forces and the other will not be able to resist. The Venetians,
moved, as I believe, by the above reasons, fostered the Guelph and Ghibelline
factions in their tributary cities; and although they never allowed them
to come to bloodshed, yet they nursed these disputes amongst them, so that
the citizens, distracted by their differences, should not unite against
them. Which, as we saw, did not afterwards turn out as expected, because,
after the rout at Vaila, one party at once took courage and seized the
state. Such methods argue, therefore, weakness in the prince, because these
factions will never be permitted in a vigorous principality; such methods
for enabling one the more easily to manage subjects are only useful in
times of peace, but if war comes this policy proves fallacious.
4. Without doubt princes become great
when they overcome the difficulties and obstacles by which they are confronted,
and therefore fortune, especially when she desires to make a new prince
great, who has a greater necessity to earn renown than an hereditary one,
causes enemies to arise and form designs against him, in order that he
may have the opportunity of overcoming them, and by them to mount higher,
as by a ladder which his enemies have raised. For this reason many consider
that a wise prince, when he has the opportunity, ought with craft to foster
some animosity against himself, so that, having crushed it, his renown
may rise higher.
5. Princes, especially new ones,
have found more fidelity and assistance in those men who in the beginning
of their rule were distrusted than among those who in the beginning were
trusted. Pandolfo Petrucci, Prince of Siena, ruled his state more by those
who had been distrusted than by others. But on this question one cannot
speak generally, for it varies so much with the individual; I will only
say this, that those men who at the commencement of a princedom have been
hostile, if they are of a description to need assistance to support themselves,
can always be gained over with the greatest ease, and they will be tightly
held to serve the prince with fidelity, inasmuch as they know it to be
very necessary for them to cancel by deeds the bad impression which he
had formed of them; and thus the prince always extracts more profit from
them than from those who, serving him in too much security, may neglect
his affairs. And since the matter demands it, I must not fail to warn a
prince, who by means of secret favours has acquired a new state, that he
must well consider the reasons which induced those to favour him who did
so; and if it be not a natural affection towards him, but only discontent
with their government, then he will only keep them friendly with great
trouble and difficulty, for it will be impossible to satisfy them. And
weighing well the reasons for this in those examples which can be taken
from ancient and modern affairs, we shall find that it is easier for the
prince to make friends of those men who were contented under the former
government, and are therefore his enemies, than of those who, being discontented
with it, were favourable to him and encouraged him to seize it.
6. It has been a custom with princes,
in order to hold their states more securely, to build fortresses that may
serve as a bridle and bit to those who might design to work against them,
and as a place of refuge from a first attack. I praise this system because
it has been made use of formerly. Notwithstanding that, Messer Nicolo Vitelli
in our times has been seen to demolish two fortresses in Citta di Castello
so that he might keep that state; Guidubaldo, Duke of Urbino, on returning
to his dominion, whence he had been driven by Cesare Borgia, razed to the
foundations all the fortresses in that province, and considered that without
them it would be more difficult to lose it; the Bentivoglio returning to
Bologna came to a similar decision. Fortresses, therefore, are useful or
not according to circumstances; if they do you good in one way they injure
you in another. And this question can be reasoned thus: the prince who
has more to fear from the people than from foreigners ought to build fortresses,
but he who has more to fear from foreigners than from the people ought
to leave them alone. The castle of Milan, built by Francesco Sforza, has
made, and will make, more trouble for the house of Sforza than any other
disorder in the state. For this reason the best possible fortress is- not
to be hated by the people, because, although you may hold the fortresses,
yet they will not save you if the people hate you, for there will never
be wanting foreigners to assist a people who have taken arms against you.
It has not been seen in our times that such fortresses have been of use
to any prince, unless to the Countess of Forli, when the Count Girolamo,
her consort, was killed; for by that means she was able to withstand the
popular attack and wait for assistance from Milan, and thus recover her
state; and the posture of affairs was such at that time that the foreigners
could not assist the people. But fortresses were of little value to her
afterwards when Cesare Borgia attacked her, and when the people, her enemy,
were allied with foreigners. Therefore it would have been safer for her,
both then and before, not to have been hated by the people than to have
had the fortresses. All these things considered then, I shall praise him
who builds fortresses as well as him who does not, and I shall blame whoever,
trusting in them, cares little about being hated by the people.
CHAPTER 21
HOW A PRINCE SHOULD CONDUCT HIMSELF
SO AS TO GAIN RENOWN
NOTHING makes a prince so much esteemed
as great enterprises and setting a fine example. We have in our time Ferdinand
of Aragon, the present King of Spain. He can almost be called a new prince,
because he has risen, by fame and glory, from being an insignificant king
to be the foremost king in Christendom; and if you will consider his deeds
you will find them all great and some of them extraordinary. In the beginning
of his reign he attacked Granada, and this enterprise was the foundation
of his dominions. He did this quietly at first and without any fear of
hindrance, for he held the minds of the barons of Castile occupied in thinking
of the war and not anticipating any innovations; thus they did not perceive
that by these means he was acquiring power and authority over them. He
was able with the money of the Church and of the people to sustain his
armies, and by that long war to lay the foundation for the military skill
which has since distinguished him. Further, always using religion as a
plea, so as to undertake greater schemes, he devoted himself with a pious
cruelty to driving out and clearing his kingdom of the Moors; nor could
there be a more admirable example, nor one more rare. Under this same cloak
he assailed Africa, he came down on Italy, he has finally attacked France;
and thus his achievements and designs have always been great, and have
kept the minds of his people in suspense and admiration and occupied with
the issue of them. And his actions have arisen in such a way, one out of
the other, that men have never been given time to work steadily against
him. Again, it much assists a prince to set unusual examples in internal
affairs, similar to those which are related of Messer Bernabo da Milano,
who, when he had the opportunity, by any one in civil life doing some extraordinary
thing, either good or bad, would take some method of rewarding or punishing
him, which would be much spoken about. And a prince ought, above all things,
always to endeavour in every action to gain for himself the reputation
of being a great and remarkable man. A prince is also respected when he
is either a true friend or a downright enemy, that to say, when, without
any reservation, he declares himself in favour of one party against the
other; which course will always be more advantageous than standing neutral;
because if two of your powerful neighbours come to blows, they are of such
a character that, if one of them conquers, you have either to fear him
or not. In either case it will always be more advantageous for you to declare
yourself and to make war strenuously; because, in the first case, if you
do not declare yourself, you will invariably fall a prey to the conqueror,
to the pleasure and satisfaction of him who has been conquered, and you
will have no reasons to offer, nor anything to protect or to shelter you.
Because he who conquers does not want doubtful friends who will not aid
him in the time of trial; and he who loses will not harbour you because
you did not willingly, sword in hand, court his fate. Antiochus went into
Greece, being sent for by the Aetolians to drive out the Romans. He sent
envoys to the Achaeans, who were friends of the Romans, exhorting them
to remain neutral; and on the other hand the Romans urged them to take
up arms. This question came to be discussed in the council of the Achaeans,
where the legate of Antiochus urged them to stand neutral. To this the
Roman legate answered: "As for that which has been said, that it is better
and more advantageous for your state not to interfere in our war, nothing
can be more erroneous; because by not interfering you will be left, without
favour or consideration, the guerdon of the conqueror." Thus it will always
happen that he who is not your friend will demand your neutrality, whilst
he who is your friend will entreat you to declare yourself with arms. And
irresolute princes, to avoid present dangers, generally follow the neutral
path, and are generally ruined. But when a prince declares himself gallantly
in favour of one side, if the party with whom he allies himself conquers,
although the victor may be powerful and may have him at his mercy, yet
he is indebted to him, and there is established a bond of amity; and men
are never so shameless as to become a monument of ingratitude by oppressing
you. Victories after all are never so complete that the victor must not
show some regard, especially to justice. But if he with whom you ally yourself
loses, you may be sheltered by him, and whilst he is able he may aid you,
and you become companions in a fortune that may rise again. In the second
case, when those who fight are of such a character that you have no anxiety
as to who may conquer, so much the more is it greater prudence to be allied,
because you assist at the destruction of one by the aid of another who,
if he had been wise, would have saved him; and conquering, as it is impossible
that he should not with your assistance, he remains at your discretion.
And here it is to be noted that a prince ought to take care never to make
an alliance with one more powerful than himself for the purpose of attacking
others, unless necessity compels him, as is said above; because if he conquers
you are at his discretion, and princes ought to avoid as much as possible
being at the discretion of any one. The Venetians joined with France against
the Duke of Milan, and this alliance, which caused their ruin, could have
been avoided. But when it cannot be avoided, as happened to the Florentines
when the Pope and Spain sent armies to attack Lombardy, then in such a
case, for the above reasons, the prince ought to favour one of the parties.
Never let any Government imagine that it can choose perfectly safe courses;
rather let it expect to have to take very doubtful ones, because it is
found in ordinary affairs that one never seeks to avoid one trouble without
running into another; but prudence consists in knowing how to distinguish
the character of troubles, and for choice to take the lesser evil. A prince
ought also to show himself a patron of ability, and to honour the proficient
in every art. At the same time he should encourage his citizens to practise
their callings peaceably, both in commerce and agriculture, and in every
other following, so that the one should not be deterred from improving
his possessions for fear lest they be taken away from him or another from
opening up trade for fear of taxes; but the prince ought to offer rewards
to whoever wishes to do these things and designs in any way to honour his
city or state. Further, he ought to entertain the people with festivals
and spectacles at convenient seasons of the year; and as every city is
divided into guilds or into societies, he ought to hold such bodies in
esteem, and associate with them sometimes, and show himself an example
of courtesy and liberality; nevertheless, always maintaining the majesty
of his rank, for this he must never consent to abate in anything.
CHAPTER 22
CONCERNING THE SECRETARIES OF PRINCES
THE choice of servants is of no little
importance to a prince, and they are good or not according to the discrimination
of the prince. And the first opinion which one forms of a prince, and of
his understanding, is by observing the men he has around him; and when
they are capable and faithful he may always be considered wise, because
he has known how to recognize the capable and to keep them faithful. But
when they are otherwise one cannot form a good opinion of him, for the
prime error which he made was in choosing them. There were none who knew
Messer Antonio da Venafro as the servant of Pandolfo Petrucci, Prince of
Siena, who would not consider Pandolfo to be a very clever man in having
Venafro for his servant. Because there are three classes of intellects:
one which comprehends by itself; another which appreciates what others
comprehend; and a third which neither comprehends by itself nor by the
showing of others; the first is the most excellent, the second is good,
the third is useless. Therefore, it follows necessarily that, if Pandolfo
was not in the first rank, he was in the second, for whenever one has judgment
to know good or bad when it is said and done, although he himself may not
have the initiative, yet he can recognize the good and the bad in his servant,
and the one he can praise and the other correct; thus the servant cannot
hope to deceive him, and is kept honest. But to enable a prince to form
an opinion of his servant there is one test which never falls; when you
see the servant thinking more of his own interests than of yours, and seeking
inwardly his own profit in everything, such a man will never make a good
servant, nor will you ever be able to trust him; because he who has the
state of another in his hands ought never to think of himself, but always
of his prince, and never pay any attention to matters in which the prince
is not concerned. On the other to keep his servant honest the prince ought
to study him, honouring him, enriching him, doing him kindnesses, sharing
with him the honours and cares; and at the same time let him see that he
cannot stand alone, so that many honours not make him desire more, many
riches make him wish for more, and that many cares may make him dread changes.
When, therefore, servants, and princes towards servants, are thus disposed,
they can trust each other, but when it is otherwise, the end will always
be disastrous for either one or the other.
CHAPTER 23
HOW FLATTERERS SHOULD BE AVOIDED
I DO NOT wish to leave out an important
branch of this subject, for it is a danger from which princes are with
difficulty preserved, unless they are very careful and discriminating.
It is that of flatterers, of whom courts arc full, because men are so self-complacent
in their own affairs, and in a way so deceived in them, that they are preserved
with difficulty from this pest, and if they wish to defend themselves they
run the danger of falling into contempt. Because there is no other way
of guarding oneself from flatterers except letting men understand that
to tell you the truth does not offend you; but when every one may tell
you the truth, respect for you abates. Therefore a wise prince ought to
hold a third course by choosing the wise men in his state, and giving to
them only the liberty of speaking the truth to him, and then only of those
things of which he inquires, and of none others; but he ought to question
them upon everything, and listen to their opinions, and afterwards form
his own conclusions. With these councillors, separately and collectively,
he ought to carry himself in such a way that each of them should know that,
the more freely he shall speak, the more he shall be preferred; outside
of these, he should listen to no one, pursue the thing resolved on, and
be steadfast in his resolutions. He who does otherwise is either overthrown
by flatterers, or is so often changed by varying opinions that he falls
into contempt. I wish on this subject to adduce a modern example. Fra Luca,
the man of affairs to Maximilian, the present emperor, speaking of his
majesty, said: He consulted with no one, yet never got his own way in anything.
This arose because of his following a practice the opposite to the above;
for the emperor is a secretive man- he does not communicate his designs
to any one, nor does he receive opinions on them. But as in carrying them
into effect they become revealed and known, they are at once obstructed
by those men whom he has around him, and he, being pliant, is diverted
from them. Hence it follows that those things he does one day he undoes
the next, and no one ever understands what he wishes or intends to do,
and no one can rely on his resolutions. A prince, therefore, ought always
to take counsel, but only when he wishes and not when others wish; he ought
rather to discourage every one from offering advice unless he asks it;
but, however, he ought to be a constant inquirer, and afterwards a patient
listener concerning the things of which he inquired; also, on learning
that any one, on any consideration, has not told him the truth, he should
let his anger be felt. And if there are some who think that a prince who
conveys an impression of his wisdom is not so through his own ability,
but through the good advisers that he has around him, beyond doubt they
are deceived, because this is an axiom which never fails: that a prince
who is not wise himself will never take good advice, unless by chance he
has yielded his affairs entirely to one person who happens to be a very
prudent man. In this case indeed he may be well governed, but it would
not be for long, because such a governor would in a short time take away
his state from him. But if a prince who is not experienced should take
counsel from more than one he will never get united counsels, nor will
he know how to unite them. Each of the counsellors will think of his own
interests, and the prince will not know how to control them or to see through
them. And they are not to be found otherwise, because men will always prove
untrue to you unless they are kept honest by constraint. Therefore it must
be inferred that good counsels, whencesoever they come, are born of the
wisdom of the prince, and not the wisdom of the prince from good counsels.
CHAPTER 24
THE PRINCES OF ITALY HAVE LOST THEIR
STATES
THE previous suggestions, carefully
observed, will enable a new prince to appear well established, and render
him at once more secure and fixed in the state than if he had been long
seated there. For the actions of a new prince are more narrowly observed
than those of an hereditary one, and when they are seen to be able they
gain more men and bind far tighter than ancient blood; because men are
attracted more by the present than by the past, and when they find the
present good they enjoy it and seek no further; they will also make the
utmost defence for a prince if he fails them not in other things. Thus
it will be a double glory to him to have established a new principality,
and adorned and strengthened it with good laws, good arms, good allies,
and with a good example; so will it be a double disgrace to him who, born
a prince, shall lose his state by want of wisdom. And if those seigniors
are considered who have lost their states in Italy in our times, such as
the King of Naples, the Duke of Milan, and others, there will be found
in them, firstly, one common defect in regard to arms from the causes which
have been discussed at length; in the next place, some one of them will
be seen, either to have had the people hostile, or if he has had the people
friendly, he has not known how to secure the nobles. In the absence of
these defects states that have power enough to keep an army in the field
cannot be lost. Philip of Macedon, not the father of Alexander the Great,
but he who was conquered by Titus Quintius, had not much territory compared
to the greatness of the Romans and of Greece who attacked him, yet being
a warlike man who knew how to attract the people and secure the nobles,
he sustained the war against his enemies for many years, and if in the
end he lost the dominion of some cities, nevertheless he retained the kingdom.
Therefore, do not let our princes accuse fortune for the loss of their
principalities after so many years' possession, but rather their own sloth,
because in quiet times they never thought there could be a change (it is
a common defect in man not to make any provision in the calm against the
tempest), and when afterwards the bad times came they thought of flight
and not of defending themselves, and they hoped that the people, disgusted
with the insolence of the conquerors, would recall them. This course, when
others fail, may be good, but it is very bad to have neglected all other
expedients for that, since you would never wish to fall because you trusted
to be able to find someone later on to restore you. This again either does
not happen, or, if it does, it will not be for your security, because that
deliverance is of no avail which does not depend upon yourself; those only
are reliable, certain, and durable that depend on yourself and your valour.
CHAPTER 25
WHAT FORTUNE CAN EFFECT IN HUMAN AFFAIRS,
AND HOW TO WITHSTAND HER
IT is not unknown to me how many men
have had, and still have, the opinion that the affairs of the world are
in such wise governed by fortune and by God that men with their wisdom
cannot direct them and that no one can even help them; and because of this
they would have us believe that it is not necessary to labour much in affairs,
but to let chance govern them. This opinion has been more credited in our
times because of the great changes in affairs which have been seen, and
may still be seen, every day, beyond all human conjecture. Sometimes pondering
over this, I am in some degree inclined to their opinion. Nevertheless,
not to extinguish our free will, I hold it to be true that Fortune is the
arbiter of one-half of our actions, but that she still leaves us to direct
the other half, or perhaps a little less. I compare her to one of those
raging rivers, which when in flood overflows the plains, sweeping away
trees and buildings, bearing away the soil from place to place; everything
flies before it, all yield to its violence, without being able in any way
to withstand it; and yet, though its nature be such, it does not follow
therefore that men, when the weather becomes fair, shall not make provision,
both with defences and barriers, in such a manner that, rising again, the
waters may pass away by canal, and their force be neither so unrestrained
nor so dangerous. So it happens with fortune, who shows her power where
valour has not prepared to resist her, and thither she turns her forces
where she knows that barriers and defences have not been raised to constrain
her. And if you will consider Italy, which is the seat of these changes,
and which has given to them their impulse, you will see it to be an open
country without barriers and without any defence. For if it had been defended
by proper valour, as are Germany, Spain, and France, either this invasion
would not have made the great changes it has made or it would not have
come at all. And this I consider enough to say concerning resistance to
fortune in general. But confining myself more to the particular, I say
that a prince may be seen happy to-day and ruined to-morrow without having
shown any change of disposition or character. This, I believe, arises firstly
from causes that have already been discussed at length, namely, that the
prince who relies entirely upon fortune is lost when it changes. I believe
also that he will be successful who directs his actions according to the
spirit of the times, and that he whose actions do not accord with the times
will not be successful. Because men are seen, in affairs that lead to the
end which every man has before him, namely, glory and riches, to get there
by various methods; one with caution, another with haste; one by force,
another by skill; one by patience, another by its opposite; and each one
succeeds in reaching the goal by a different method. One can also see of
two cautious men the one attain his end, the other fail; and similarly,
two men by different observances are equally successful, the one being
cautious, the other impetuous; all this arises from nothing else than whether
or not they conform in their methods to the spirit of the times. This follows
from what I have said, that two men working differently bring about the
same effect, and of two working similarly, one attains his object and the
other does not. Changes in estate also issue from this, for if, to one
who governs himself with caution and patience, times and affairs converge
in such a way that his administration is successful, his fortune is made;
but if times and affairs change, he is ruined if he does not change his
course of action. But a man is not often found sufficiently circumspect
to know how to accommodate himself to the change, both because he cannot
deviate from what nature inclines him to, and also because, having always
prospered by acting in one way, he cannot be persuaded that it is well
to leave it; and, therefore, the cautious man, when it is time to turn
adventurous, does not know how to do it, hence he is ruined; but had he
changed his conduct with the times fortune would not have changed. Pope
Julius II went to work impetuously in all his affairs, and found the times
and circumstances conform so well to that line of action that he always
met with success. Consider his first enterprise against Bologna, Messer
Giovanni Bentivogli being still alive. The Venetians were not agreeable
to it, nor was the King of Spain, and he had the enterprise still under
discussion with the King of France; nevertheless he personally entered
upon the expedition with his accustomed boldness and energy, a move which
made Spain and the Venetians stand irresolute and passive, the latter from
fear, the former from desire to recover all the kingdom of Naples; on the
other hand, he drew after him the King of France, because that king, having
observed the movement, and desiring to make the Pope his friend so as to
humble the Venetians, found it impossible to refuse him soldiers without
manifestly offending him. Therefore Julius with his impetuous action accomplished
what no other pontiff with simple human wisdom could have done; for if
he had waited in Rome until he could get away, with his plans arranged
and everything fixed, as any other pontiff would have done, he would never
have succeeded. Because the King of France would have made a thousand excuses,
and the others would have raised a thousand fears. I will leave his other
actions alone, as they were all alike, and they all succeeded, for the
shortness of his life did not let him experience the contrary; but if circumstances
had arisen which required him to go cautiously, his ruin would have followed,
because he would never have deviated from those ways to which nature inclined
him. I conclude therefore that, fortune being changeful and mankind steadfast
in their ways, so long as the two are in agreement men are successful,
but unsuccessful when they fall out. For my part I consider that it is
better to be adventurous than cautious, because fortune is a woman, and
if you wish to keep her under it is necessary to beat and ill-use her;
and it is seen that she allows herself to be mastered by the adventurous
rather than by those who go to work more coldly. She is, therefore, always,
woman-like, a lover of young men, because they are less cautious, more
violent, and with more audacity command her.
CHAPTER 26
AN EXHORTATION TO LIBERATE ITALY FROM
THE BARBARIANS
HAVING carefully considered the subject
of the above discourses, and wondering within myself whether the present
times were propitious to a new prince, and whether there were the elements
that would give an opportunity to a wise and virtuous one to introduce
a new order of things which would do honour to him and good to the people
of this country, it appears to me that so many things concur to favour
a new prince that I never knew a time more fit than the present. And if,
as I said, it was necessary that the people of Israel should be captive
so as to make manifest the ability of Moses; that the Persians should be
oppressed by the Medes so as to discover the greatness of the soul of Cyrus;
and that the Athenians should be dispersed to illustrate the capabilities
of Theseus: then at the present time, in order to discover the virtue of
an Italian spirit, it was necessary that Italy should be reduced to the
extremity she is now in, that she should be more enslaved than the Hebrews,
more oppressed than the Persians, more scattered than the Athenians; without
head, without order, beaten, despoiled, torn, overrun; and to have endured
every kind of desolation. Although lately some spark may have been shown
by one, which made us think he was ordained by God for our redemption,
nevertheless it was afterwards seen, in the height of his career, that
fortune rejected him; so that Italy, left as without life, waits for him
who shall yet heal her wounds and put an end to the ravaging and plundering
of Lombardy, to the swindling and taxing of the kingdom and of Tuscany,
and cleanse those sores that for long have festered. It is seen how she
entreats God to send someone who shall deliver her from these wrongs and
barbarous insolencies. It is seen also that she is ready and willing to
follow a banner if only someone will raise it. Nor is there to be seen
at present one in whom she can place more hope than in your illustrious
house, with its valour and fortune, favoured by God and by the Church of
which it is now the chief, and which could be made the head of this redemption.
This will not be difficult if you will recall to yourself the actions and
lives of the men I have named. And although they were great and wonderful
men, yet they were men, and each one of them had no more opportunity than
the present offers, for their enterprises were neither more just nor easier
than this, nor was God more their friend than He is yours. With us there
is great justice, because that war is just which is necessary, and arms
are hallowed when there is no other hope but in them. Here there is the
greatest willingness, and where the willingness is great the difficulties
cannot be great if you will only follow those men to whom I have directed
your attention. Further than this, how extraordinarily the ways of God
have been manifested beyond example: the sea is divided, a cloud has led
the way, the rock has poured forth water, it has rained manna, everything
has contributed to your greatness; you ought to do the rest. God is not
willing to do everything, and thus take away our free will and that share
of glory which belongs to us. And it is not to be wondered at if none of
the above-named Italians have been able to accomplish all that is expected
from your illustrious house; and if in so many revolutions in Italy, and
in so many campaigns, it has always appeared as if military virtue were
exhausted, this has happened because the old order of things was not good,
and none of us have known how to find a new one. And nothing honours a
man more than to establish new laws and new ordinances when he himself
was newly risen. Such things when they are well founded and dignified will
make him revered and admired, and in Italy there are not wanting opportunities
to bring such into use in every form. Here there is great valour in the
limbs whilst it fails in the head. Look attentively at the duels and the
hand-to-hand combats, how superior the Italians are in strength, dexterity,
and subtlety. But when it comes to armies they do not bear comparison,
and this springs entirely from the insufficiency of the leaders, since
those who are capable are not obedient, and each one seems to himself to
know, there having never been any one so distinguished above the rest,
either by valour or fortune, that others would yield to him. Hence it is
that for so long a time, and during so much fighting in the past twenty
years, whenever there has been an army wholly Italian, it has always given
a poor account of itself; as witness Taro, Alessandria, Capua, Genoa, Vaila,
Bologna, Mestre. If, therefore, your illustrious house wishes to follow
those remarkable men who have redeemed their country, it is necessary before
all things, as a true foundation for every enterprise, to be provided with
your own forces, because there can be no more faithful, truer, or better
soldiers. And although singly they are good, altogether they will be much
better when they find themselves commanded by their prince, honoured by
him, and maintained at his expense. Therefore it is necessary to be prepared
with such arms, so that you can be defended against foreigners by Italian
valour. And although Swiss and Spanish infantry may be considered very
formidable, nevertheless there is a defect in both, by reason of which
a third order would not only be able to oppose them, but might be relied
upon to overthrow them. For the Spaniards cannot resist cavalry, and the
Switzers are afraid of infantry whenever they encounter them in close combat.
Owing to this, as has been and may again be seen, the Spaniards are unable
to resist French cavalry, and the Switzers are overthrown by infantry.
And although a complete proof of this latter cannot be shown, nevertheless
there was some evidence of it at the battle of Ravenna, when the Spanish
infantry were confronted by German battalions, who follow the same tactics
as the Swiss; when the Spaniards, by agility of body and with the aid of
their shields, got in under the pikes of the Germans and stood out of danger,
able to attack, while the Germans stood helpless, and, if the cavalry had
not dashed up, all would have been over with them. It is possible, therefore,
knowing the defects of both these infantries, to invent a new one, which
will resist cavalry and not be afraid of infantry; this need not create
a new order of arms, but a variation upon the old. And these are the kind
of improvements which confer reputation and power upon a new prince. This
opportunity, therefore, ought not to be allowed to pass for letting Italy
at last see her liberator appear. Nor can one express the love with which
he would be received in all those provinces which have suffered so much
from these foreign scourings, with what thirst for revenge, with what stubborn
faith, with what devotion, with what tears. What door would be closed to
him? Who would refuse obedience to him? What envy would hinder him? What
Italian would refuse him homage? To all of us this barbarous dominion stinks.
Let, therefore, your illustrious house take up this charge with that courage
and hope with which all just enterprises are undertaken, so that under
its standard our native country may be ennobled, and under its auspices
may be verified that saying of Petrarch: Virtu contro al Furore Prendera
l'arme, e fia il combatter corto: Che l'antico valore Negli italici cuor
non e ancor morto. Virtue against fury shall advance the fight, And
it i' th' combat soon shall put to flight; For the old Roman, valour is
not dead, Nor in th' Italians' breasts extinguished.
- THE END -
|