13. WESTERN RATIONALISM
RATIONALISM REPLACES THE CHRISTIAN WORLDVIEW
CONTENTS
Understanding the Spirit of the Times
Descartes ... and the birth of the "Age of Reason
Rationalism in the late 1600s: Newton, Leibniz and Locke
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
The reaction to such rationalism: British empiricism
Immanuel Kant
The French Revolution plunges ahead, seeking a rational utopia
The textual material on this webpage is drawn directly from my work
America – The Covenant Nation © 2021, Volume One, pages 387-398.
UNDERSTANDING THE SPIRIT OF THE TIMES |
Thus far we have been looking at the Progressivist
Era largely in terms of its material quality, presented in terms of the
vast material wealth that a number of Americans enjoyed, or the lack of
that same wealth suffered by others, and the politics involved in
trying to make such materialism work to the greater advantage of
individuals, groups of individuals, and even the nation as a whole. We
have looked at individuals whose energy made much of this possible, the
captains of industry and finance (or "robber barons" if you were
distressed at how poorly this rising wealth was distributed more
broadly among the American population) and the inventors and technical
innovators whose ideas kept the Progressivist Era moving ever forward
to new and truly amazing material inventions and developments.
The Age of Progress and the "Revolution of Rising Expectations."
But at this point we want to look more
closely at the spirit of the times, the intellectual, moral and
spiritual character of American culture, and the forces that shaped it.
It is important to note that the very idea of wealth, or of poverty, is
not itself an objective matter, like an automobile, a large or small
house, the clothes someone wears, the humble or exotic nature of what
is found on the dinner table, etc. Indeed, the very poor were actually
better off materially than the middle classes of just a couple of
centuries earlier, when the planet was less able to support a large
human population. People of course still suffered from fatigue, hunger,
disease, and just plain aging. But the profile of Westerners at the
turn of the century demonstrated actually a vitality among vast numbers
that would have been unthinkable just generations earlier. Yet poverty
was there, bitter poverty for some, especially for those (mostly in
America's fast-rising cities and industrial towns) whose lives
contrasted so sharply with the lives of the very, very wealthy, who
benefitted awesomely from the labors of these poor souls.
Yet the poor souls were actually doing
much better materially than their medieval counterparts. But
expectations were there nonetheless that justice was not being well
served by the way America's vast wealth was being distributed.
Certainly that idea formed much of the drive behind the Progressivist
Movement. If the gap between rich and poor (as it has always been
through the ages) had remained largely unchanged, little would have
been said about the matter. It would have been accepted as the normal
scheme of things (as it was for centuries). But things were changing
rapidly, and with them the expectations of the benefits, the fruits of
change. And those expectations, emotional and intellectual, were the
reality that people actually responded to. And they were rising as fast
or faster than the actual material growth of the American economy and
technology.
With time the simplest of Americans would
be drawn into the world of the new gadgets and lifestyle possibilities,
because such fast-developing wealth needed the American people
themselves (what ultimately we would identify as the consumer) to
absorb the end products of the economic system. Henry Ford understood
this principle very well, and got very rich from it.
But America's reality at the turn of the
century was not really in just interesting material statistics, but in
the fact that America was going through a "Revolution of Rising
Expectations." And those expectations were the reality that Americans
responded to.
So at this point we turn to the
all-important question: what exactly were those expectations? What was
it exactly that Americans were thinking concerning their situations,
their lives?
The mechanics of social thinking
People themselves are actually not very
innovative thinkers, but borrow thought from larger society.
Individuals have personalities of their own, of course. But even more
importantly they develop social personalities, a sense of personhood
drawn from the cultural themes around them, themes that others generate
for them individually (opinion leaders) and collectively, out of a
commonly-perceived social experience they find themselves in. In other
words, people mostly follow the crowd of one kind or another. And what
they do, how they act, how they react, is shaped not so much by their
own personal reasoning as much as by the reasoning of the social group
they identify themselves with – or actually groups, some cooperating to
give even more cohesion and strength to a person’s social identity, or
on the other hand clashing, causing much personal confusion and
frustration.
So again, what were Americans thinking at
this time? How were they redesigning their personal universe? Something
big was going on – because all this material change was stirring new
cultural ideas that challenged Americans to rethink their world.
Europe's lead in the emerging "Post Christian" culture
One more point. America itself was not
doing this in isolation, but was itself participating (mostly
willingly) in a larger rethink of all of Western Civilization. This
civilization used to be called "Christian Civilization." But although
people still used that language in describing a desirable Christian
world, a larger Christian moral code, a set of Christian social goals,
the reality was that Christianity was not any single social-political
idea – as the violent Protestant-Catholic Wars of Religion of the
early-mid 1600s clearly demonstrated. In any case, new ideas were on
the rise within this Christian West that had no connection with the
idea of the sovereign rule of God or the saving power of Jesus's
lordship over the world. Something else in the West was fast replacing
Christian culture, a new culture identified by various labels:
Materialism, Empiricism, Darwinism, Secularism, Humanism, Socialism,
etc., all of which developed from this rising sense of man's own powers
to conquer and reshape the world by his own designs, his own logic, his
own powers, his own ability to see his human programs put into place to
make this world a much, much better place. All of this mental energy
was thus serving in different ways to give Western Civilization a new
and very aggressive character.
It was all very heady stuff. Just in
looking around at all the material bounty that came with this
new-think, it is not surprising how very compelling this new culture
was. Christianity, with its call for humility in approaching life and
its emphasis in trusting God alone to get things right, just did not
appear to be the sure and certain formula for acquiring the offerings
of this new world of material bounty. And thus people's minds and
hearts were fast shifting to this exciting new world of what could be
summed up basically as Secular Humanism.
In this development, Europe was way ahead
of America. But America was learning quickly. America had its own new
ideas about life. But by and large Americans found themselves greatly
attracted to the high level of social thought coming from Europe. In
fact it was considered to be the height of sophistication to go off to
Europe to study (the reverse was hardly the case yet!). Indeed, in the
realm of higher thought, America mostly found itself simply responding
to European developments that were well underway across the Atlantic.
And that would even take America right
into the Great War (World War One, 1914-1918) which America long
debated before making the fateful decision to jump into the event.
And thus, for much of this section, we want to look at Europe, and the
thought processes going on there, and how that shaped global events,
ones that formerly isolationist America avoided during its fragile
early development. Now America found itself unable to resist the
European dynamic but instead joined in – unfortunately in full measure.
|
DESCARTES ... AND THE BIRTH OF THE "AGE OF REASON" (Early
1600s) |
The very ancient roots of the central problem
arising with the adulation (even worship) of Human Reason
The use of human reason rather than reliance on
divine guidance is not a new issue on this planet. It certainly did not
arrive for the first time with Europe's step into the Modern Age,
considered by historians to have started somewhere around the mid-1600s, with the end of the Wars of Religion.
The very ancient Judeo-Christian Bible
begins its narration with this very issue – immediately after the story
of divine creation. The narration centers on man's first temptation: to
go his own way rather than to go with God. That is the essence of the
story of the Garden of Eden when God had forbidden Adam and Eve to eat
of the Tree of the Knowledge of Good and Evil. He did not explain why,
because they were still obedient to God rather than deciding themselves
what was good and what was evil. However, the Tempter in the form of a
serpent soon intervened in the story to put the thought in the minds of
this primal couple, that knowing on their own what was good and what
was evil would make them like God. That was (and still is) quite a
temptation, one they could not or anyway would not resist. And so, they
ate of the forbidden fruit, and troubles began immediately.
Western Civilization continues to wrestle with this same issue
It's a great story, absolutely ageless in
its wisdom, as Europe was already discovering. And if they had not
learned about the Truth of the narrative in observing the events of the
Wars of Religion (also known as the Thirty Years' War of 1618-1648) or
the French Revolution at the end of the 1700s, they were about to have
the issue put squarely in front of them again in the form of the Great
War (World War One, 1914-1918), which, unknown to them, was about to
break out in seemingly unprecedented fury. But that part of the story
belongs to our next chapter.
But in any case, let's at this point take
our story of Western Civilization's effort to make sense of this newly
emerging world, all the way back to Europe during the times of the
European Enlightenment, beginning in the later 1600s, truly blossoming
in the 1700s, and challenging in so many different ways the 1800s.
Looking at the birth and development of these modern trends of social
thought and action should help us not only to understand how we got
this way, but also the difficulties we will have if we do not learn
from the past.
We have already discussed Locke and
Rousseau in some detail. But they were children of the European
Enlightenment, not its founders.
The Puritans were actually major contributors
to this emerging "Enlightenment"
The Puritans were actually major
contributors to this emerging "Enlightenment." This "Age of
Enlightenment" had its origins in the early 1600s, with the rise of
"natural philosophy" – something we today term as "science." Very
active in this matter of the "philosophy of nature" were the English
Puritans, led by such intellectuals as Francis Bacon, who at the turn
of the 1600s celebrated the new discoveries of the workings of the
natural world … seeing the hand of an incredibly awesome God in the
newly discovered grand designs of nature. Bacon's "science" was treated
as almost an act of worship ... as it would be for so many of the other
Puritans – who, for the same reason (seeing their natural philosophy as
a witness to the glory of God), took the lead in England's scientific
revolution that broke forth in the 1600s. And much the same was the
case for the Puritans' Calvinist cousins over in the Netherlands!
Descartes (early 1600s) challenges Christian Truth
with a new reliance on Pure Reason
But
at approximately the same time, the Frenchman René Descartes wrestled
with the epistemological problem of understanding how we can be certain
that what we claim to be true is indeed true – because there is such a
huge gap that separates our mind from what we believe we see out there.
How do we actually know what is true and what is not?
This was not just some philosopher's idle
question. Descartes was living at a time in which the wars between
Catholics and Protestants and between rising monarchs in different
parts of Europe were constant and having a deadly effect on European
society. Each of the contenders justified his brutal violence on the
basis of one or another truth-claim. So Descartes took up the challenge
of trying to lay out a basis by which the contenders could pursue these
truth-claims logically, rather than violently (presuming that these
contenders were indeed all that interested in Truth rather than just
domination).
Descartes observed that the world around
us operated purely mechanically (or mathematically), and that if we
disciplined our minds to work in the same way (rationally or
mathematically) we could actually close that gap between our minds and
the surrounding world. There was no need for inspiration, no need to
rely on tradition or the conventional teachings of society. Man was
fully capable of arriving at all truths – even able to prove the
existence of God – simply through the exercise of precise human reason.
With that Cartesian challenge, the Age of Reason was off and running.
For more information on Descartes
RATIONALISM IN THE LATE 1600s: NEWTON, LEIBNIZ AND LOCKE |
Three individuals stand out in particular in the
follow-up (the later 1600s) to Descartes' birth of the Age of Reason:
the two Englishmen Isaac Newton and John Locke and the German Gottfried
Wilhelm Leibniz.
Leibniz and Newton were both brilliant
mathematicians. Both seemed to have discovered calculus at about the
same time (around 1670). Leibniz tended to follow more closely the lead
of Descartes and other Rationalists on the European continent in
believing that pure reason, built simply on logical principles arrived
at through clear thought, could design a perfect world – and was
optimistic that such was soon possible.
Newton tended more to the empirical side
(typical of the British), believing that nothing could be considered
true until it had been observed to actually work in the real world. But
he was also something of a Christian mystic, which in general the
continental school of Rationalism rejected completely.
We have already met Locke (a friend of
Newton's) who too believed in the power of human reason to solve life's
various problems, whatever they might be. Locke, like Newton, was also
a highly empirical philosopher who stressed the importance of putting
our ideas to the test of observing their success (or failure) in the
actual world of people and things.
We also know that Locke was very much a
social philosopher. But he was also a student of human psychology, able
to put the two worlds of the individual and society together in a
rational order. His understanding was that human thought is importantly
a collective matter, shaped by the thinking of the larger social world
and the particular experiences that this social world was facing and
how a society interpreted those experiences. But again, his belief was
that this social world could be – must be – improved through the
careful thinking through of life's processes, in order to bring life
closer to perfection.
Locke and his writings would go on to
influence deeply the philosophy of most of the social philosophers of
the 1700s (including importantly Thomas Jefferson).

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz

Isaac Newton

John Locke
For more information on Leibniz
For more information on Newton
For more information on Locke
Rousseau and early Romanticism
Of
a very special or distinct philosophical contribution to the
discussions of 1700s France was Jean Jacques Rousseau. He was to have a
huge impact on the thinking of the European continent's Age of
Enlightenment (the 1700s).
He was French-cultured Swiss whose writings, especially The Social
Contract (1762), were very popular in France. He raised the question of
political sovereignty, where it was lodged and how it functioned to
best serve the people.
Rousseau claimed that originally man
lived in some kind of simple natural state of harmony, without laws or
government. But life had evolved over time into a more complex form –
civilization – requiring as it developed greater mutual dependence
among men for the orderly working of society, and thus also a more
complex system of moral instruction or law to guide this more complex
society. Man accordingly had to give up his total personal sovereignty
to come under the protection and nurture of more complex society. But
he was giving it up not to some ruling individual but to the larger
idea of the society as a whole, the general will – in particular its
laws, which were the clearest expression of a people's general will.
The laws, not any particular individuals,
were the locus of sovereignty in the truly good society. Unfortunately,
ignorance of this good had clouded people's political understanding,
causing them to slip into all forms of political tyranny (absolute rule
over society by particular individuals such as kings and dukes, which
was the general pattern of his day).
Rousseau's hope was to open men's eyes to
the understanding of what was truly right and good about society, that
such knowledge would free men to usher in a good or utopian society
that was truly the right of everyone to enjoy, not just the privileged
few. All the superfluous fluff of decadent civilization (in particular
French civilization as it was viewed in his own time) would be simply
swept away by the opening of the eyes of the people to the Truth.
With the Ancien R gime
(the Old Order comprised of the officers of the king and church that
dominated all European society in the 1700s) thus swept away, society
would be free to create or contract a social system as simple and basic
as possible, a social system directed by a set of basic laws that
restored to man his fundamental liberties, allowing him to live as
close to the original state of nature as possible.
The French were strongly impacted by
Rousseau's theories – as have been many revolutionary-minded secular
philosophers since Rousseau (as well as modern "hippies" trying to go
back to nature in simple communal living). Rousseau's vision of
primitive society even found its way into the polite social gatherings
or salons of Europe's ruling classes and their intellectual tutors.
Thus it was that the future queen Marie Antoinette used to love to play
in the Versailles palace gardens (with fellow maidens at the French
court) at being a peasant girl herding her sheep. It was all so quaint,
so romantic.
The French monarchy was sick, very sick. Reform was needed. But by
Rousseau's logic, that reform was going to have to be extensive for the
good society to result. The Old Order was going to have to be set aside
in its entirety in order to make way for the new. Thus with Rousseau's
encouragement, the French political mood was becoming increasingly
revolutionary as the political debate in the late 1700s intensified in
France. |
Jean-Jacques
Rousseau
(1712-1778)
French-speaking Genevan (Swiss) philosopher, author of Discourse on Inequality and The Social
Contract, explaining his views on the relationship between the
individual
and society. |
THE REACTION TO SUCH RATIONALISM: BRITISH EMPIRICISM |
The further reaction to Europe's Rationalism
In the American colonies in the mid-1700s the
Western Enlightenment was answered by the mysteries of the Great
Awakening – led by such figures as Edwards and Whitefield, and by the
broad popular response of the common people to that dynamic. While
continental Europe in general was by-passed in that event (the British,
however, certainly had their own version of the Great Awakening),
nonetheless as the 1700s moved along, something of a strong reaction to
Rationalism also set in among some of the Continental European as well
as British philosophers and scholars, something however that had very
little to do with going back to Christian basics. That non-Christian
reaction to Rationalism would take very different forms – tending to
Empiricism in Britain and Romanticism in Continental Europe (though
varieties of Empiricism and Romanticism could be found in both
locations).
To begin with, the British were of a more
practical mindset in their love of hands-on experimentation than their
continental cousins, who loved to sit at their desks or gather at
polite salons to indulge themselves in the world of pure thought.
During the Enlightenment the British were too busy inventing new
material technologies – and developing the industries to put those
technologies to practical use – to be wasting time speculating about
hypothetical realities. They were all, by nature, Empiricists.
David Hume promotes Empiricism
In
the mid-1700s the Scottish philosopher David Hume had his own answer to
the Rationalism that infected so much of European society. As a
philosophical empiricist, the widely read and respected Hume found
sufficient Truth for life in simply observing actual behavior, and the
results it produced. Results were to Hume real Truth. Long-abiding
custom (in other words, social rules that actually worked over the long
run) were for Hume the foundations on which to build human life.
Likewise, Hume was most unimpressed by
the great intellectual "spins" that philosophers wove around
hypothetical behavior in building their great systems of thought. For
Hume reality was in the doing, not in the hypothesizing about life.
Widely studied, Hume became well-known in
his time for his skepticism about speculations about God, or great
systems of religious Truth, or the validity of "objective" ethical
systems, even the claims of science to have established an explanation
of all life in terms of cause and effect. All this was to Hume mere
intellectual humbuggery.
Hume's impact lived long after him. In
fact it was Hume that awakened the great German philosopher Kant from
his "intellectual slumber" (as Kant himself put it) and caused Kant to
undertake the task of responding to the challenge that Hume had issued
to those who would claim to understand human nature, even life itself.
For more information on Hume
Adam Smith explains capitalism
In
the meantime, the British were very busy inventing new material
technologies, and developing the industries to put those technologies
to practical use.
Building on this attitude was the fellow Scot, Adam Smith, who in his Wealth of Nations
(1776) wrote a compelling explanation of how simply letting the
competitive marketplace bring forward the material blessings of life –
and the pricing involved for such wealth – would also naturally bring
forth human progress. He was much opposed to the idea of forcing on
society the designs of utopian social planners, who would soon enough
make a mess of things with their well-reasoned schemes.
In fact, Smith was strongly opposed to
any kind of "intervention" into this market mechanism by the government
or any other outside societal institution. To Smith (and all capitalist
philosophers since then) this independence of commercial action was the
key doctrine of Capitalist philosophy.
But at the same time, Smith was highly
opposed to market insiders getting together to conspire to set prices
through a withholding of goods or services to create an artificial
scarcity. He was thus opposed to cartels, monopolies, and unions, of
any variety. He also considered the danger of rapid population growth
distorting the labor market and driving prices down to subsistence
levels. But he felt that economic growth of the whole industrial sector
would constantly increase the demand for labor and thus prevent such
cruelties from occurring.
|
Kant attempts a compromise between British Empiricism
and French Rationalism
Immanuel
Kant was something of a father to German philosophy, setting out, just
prior to the French Revolution, to locate some kind of intellectual
bridge between the powerful philosophies of French Rationalism and
British Empiricism.
Kant agreed with Hume's empiricism,
namely that essential to human knowledge is our sense experience – the
experience of the seeing, feeling, hearing, etc. of real material
objects around us. But he also agreed with the continental Rationalists
(most notably Leibniz, whose writings also were a major influence on
Kant) that knowledge is also a matter of the exercise of human reason,
in particular the use of innate human ideas ("categories") which we are
born with and which help us to organize this empirical information.
Thus Kant saw himself as closing the intellectual gap between the
British Empiricists and the Continental Rationalists.
Kant also saw himself as answering Hume's
skepticism about ever knowing with any degree of certainty the Truth of
transcendent ideas, such as moral laws or ethical principles (not to
mention the idea of Heaven itself). In Kant's Metaphysics of Morals (1785) and Critique of Practical Reason
(1788), he proposed a new moral/ethical "categorical imperative," one
that did not require the existence of God for its validity. It involved
an ingenious piece of moral logic: we ought to act in such a way that
our act could become accepted as a universal principle of behavior. If
it were not able to attain such a universal validity (because, for
instance, of an internal contradiction in logic) then that action, by
"practical reason," was obviously not to be pursued.
Taking this logic of "practical reason" a
step further, he turned to the issue of the existence of God. He agreed
with Hume that no rational argument could be given for God's existence
– that is, "pure reason" could not build a case for God's existence.
But "practical reason" could. Pursuing a traditional line of reason
that went back at least as far as Ockham in the early 1300s, Kant
claimed that human reason cannot establish the "fact" of God. But in
observing the moral instincts of people we can see (through the eyes of
faith) that there is some kind of source beyond the mere human will
itself that directs life. That higher moral grounding is by definition
God. Thus God exists. (This kind of theological reasoning did not
impress the Prussian government, which censured his work).
Finally, so impressed was Kant that we humans could live in accordance with such higher moral imperatives that in his Perpetual Peace
(1795) he laid out a vision for a new world order. Here (despite the
Reign of Terror going on in France) begins the utopian idealism that
will absorb the thoughts and aspirations of intellectuals for
generations to come.
For more information on Kant
|
THE FRENCH REVOLUTION PLUNGES AHEAD,
SEEKING A
RATIONAL UTOPIA |
Of course Rationalism was by no means dethroned by
Rousseau's Romantic reaction or the challenge of British Empiricism,
because it was pure Rationalism that drove French intellectuals (and
Paris mobs) to their violent behavior during the French Revolution, a
revolution that soon produced horrors on the scale of the Religious
Wars of the 1600s that had first inspired Rationalism. During the
violent revolution that broke out in 1789, absolute Reason brought
forward powerful people who became also absolute in their authority,
and thus highly susceptible to very sophisticated self-deception as
they murdered people by the thousands in the name of Reason.
What these Rationalists failed to see was
how easily reason, in the face of the serious challenge of ruling a
very diverse people, could be so easily twisted to serve merely their
own narrower self-interests,1 rather than the dreamy goal of serving
all the people according to some kind of higher interest they claimed
they were pursuing. What these utopian Rationalists had naively come up
against was the complex issue called reality, something of which in
their lofty world of aristocratic salons they knew virtually nothing.
Reactions to the French Revolution
With the exception of Jefferson, who
while living in France just prior to the 1789 Revolution fell entirely
in love with French Rationalism, Americans in general took the same
attitude as the (Irish) Edmund Burke, who expressed eloquently the
horror that all of Britain felt about the very barbaric results of the
noble effort of the French people trying to be entirely rational. Burke
pointed out (like Hume) that long-established tradition served the
people well and should only be reformed carefully as necessary, not
overthrown.
Like the French, the Americans at the
time were birthing a new Republic. But unlike the French, the American
Republic was built cautiously on a very limited or restricted basis on
political traditions and practices already well-established in the
colonies over the previous century and a half. Americans were not
setting up a new government built on untested new principles dreamed up
by social planners, like the French were attempting. And (as we have
already seen) the results consequently were quite different from
America to France.
The Napoleonic challenge
Eventually
(1799) France was rescued by the military dictator Napoleon from the
murderous folly of the French Revolution's "Reign of Terror"
(1792-1795) and the political chaos that followed it.
Napoleon retained technical features of
the Revolution and even improved on them, for instance, supporting the
metric system and rationalizing regional government through a new
bureaucratic system which replaced the chaotic array of multitudes of
local feudal domains each with their own laws, standards and social
interests.
Pierre Simon de Laplace gives Rationalism a new lease on life
Newton
had earlier outlined the gravitational theories designed to demonstrate
that the planets moved about the sun in accordance with immutable
mathematical principles. There were however still unexplained small
variations in Newton's computations: he had not taken into account the
gravitational attraction also working among the planets themselves.
These small variations had the ability to destabilize Newton's
mechanistic model of the solar system. But Newton was enough of a
mystic to look to God to regulate the small variations so as to keep
the whole system in order.
This idea of a small residual divine
intervention was not a satisfying concept to the French Rationalist
Laplace. He understood the universe to be totally operative under the
impersonal, mechanical laws of nature. So in 1773 he set out to give
full mathematical explanation to the motions of the heavens – in such a
way that there would be no more need to call in God as the residual
part of the equation. This he successfully completed years later an
unprecedentedly in-depth mathematical calculation of the eccentricities
in the planetary orbits, taking into account their gravitation
attraction to each other as well as to the sun as they moved through
their respective orbits. This work was eventually compiled into the
five-volume study: Celestial Mechanics (1799-1825.) And it earned him a place in the prestigious French Academy of Sciences.
It also removed the idea of God further
(if not completely) from the mechanistic cosmology that had been
unfolding over the previous century. Not even Deism could stand up to
this assault.
Indeed, the story goes that when Laplace
presented a copy of his work to Napoleon, the latter uttered a concern
that Laplace had made no mention in his work of the divine "Originator"
of this marvelous system. To this, Laplace replied quite simply: "I had
no need for that hypothesis!"
1But
isn’t this what we pay lawyers to do for us: use powerful "Reason" on
our own behalf? Isn’t this what both sides are doing in a civil
or criminal case, with its opposing lawyers each skillfully presenting
rational arguments on behalf of their particular clients before a judge
or jury? Even mobsters have well-paid lawyers to defend
rationally or "justify" their behavior in court.
| | | |